TABLE OF CONTENTS
DEDICATION..................................................................................................................ii
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT....................................................................................................iii
LIST OF
CHARTS.............................................................................................................iv
INTRODUCTION
1
CHAPTER ONE: THE REVIEW OF LITERATURE
3
I.1 - THE ORIGIN AND HISTORICAL VAGARIES OF
THE TERM «PRAGMATICS» ACCORDING TO LEVINSON ( 1983)
3
I.2 - DEFINITION OF PRAGMATICS
5
I.3 - PRAGMATICS AND DISCOURSE
CONTEXT
6
I.3.1 -Pragmatic Reference
7
I.3.2 - Presupposition
7
I.3.3 - Implicatures
8
I.3.4 - Inference
9
I.3.5 - Speech act theory
9
I.4 - THE CONTEXT OF SITUATION
11
I.5 - MODALITY
12
I.5.0 Introduction
12
I.5.1 - Defining modality
14
I.5.2 - Forms and uses of
modals
18
I.5.2.1 - The grammatical forms of English
modals
19
I.5.2.2 - Deontic use of
modals
20
I.5.2.2.1 - Request
21
I.5.2.2.2 - Permission
23
I.5.2.2.3 - Advisability
24
I.5.2.2.4 - Necessity
25
I.5.2.2.5 - Obligation
25
I.5.2.3 - Epistemic use of
modals
28
I.5.2.3.1 - Possibility
29
I.5.2.3.2 - Probability
30
I.5.2.3.3 - Certainty
31
I.5.2.4 - Epistemic use versus deontic use
of modals
33
CONCLUSION
38
CHAPTER TWO: RESEARCH METHODOLOGY
38
II.1 - APPROACH
39
II.2 - DATA COLLECTION TECHNIQUES AND
INSTRUMENTS
40
II.3 - SAMPLING
41
II.4 - PROBLEMS ENCOUNTERED IN THE FIELD
AND SOLUTIONS PROVIDED
42
II.5 - DATA ANALYSIS PROCEDURE
43
CHAPTER THREE: FINDINGS FROM OUR DATA
ANALYSIS
44
III.1 - FINDINGS FROM THE IDENTIFICATION
ITEMS
45
III.2 - FINDINGS FROM THE
EXPERIMENT
46
III.2.1 - Meaning Recognition
46
III.2.1.1 - Scores and
comments
46
III.2.1.1.1- Scores of the deontic meaning
recognition and comments
46
III.2.1.1.2 - Scores of the epistemic
meaning recognition and comments
47
III.2.1.1.3 - Scores of the deontic or/and
epistemic meaning recognition and comments
47
Chart 6: - Scores of the deontic or/and
epistemic meaning recognition and comments
48
III.2.1.1.4 - Scores of the test on
recognition and comments
48
III.2.1.1.5 - Comments on
scores
49
III.2.1.2 - Distribution of meanings to
modals
50
III.2.1.3 - Students' modality
tendency
52
III.2.1.4 - Confusion between the kinds of
meanings
53
III.2.1.5 - Confusion between the types of
meanings
55
III.2.1.6 - Comments on
recognition
56
III.2.2 - Modal Production
57
III.2.2.1 - Scores and
comments
57
III.2.2.1.1 - Scores of the deontic meaning
production and comments
57
III.2.2.1.2 - Scores of the epistemic
meaning production and comments
58
III.2.2.1.3 - Scores of the deontic or/and
epistemic meaning production and comments
58
III.2.2.1.4 - Scores of the test on
production and comments
59
III.2.2.1.5 - Partial conclusion on scores
of production
60
III.2.2.2 - Distribution of modals to
meanings
61
III.2.2.3 - Use of modals to express
ambiguity
63
III.2.2.4 - Confusion between
modals
64
III.2.2.5 - Students' preferred
modals
66
III.2.2.6 - Comments on
production
67
III.2.3 - Partial conclusions and
verification of the hypothesis
68
III.3 - PROBABLE SOURCES OF MODAL MISUSE
AND MISUNDERSTANDING
70
CHAPTER FOUR: RATIONALE OF MODALS TEACHING
AND LEARNING AND SOME SUGGESTIONS
73
IV.1 - THE RATIONALE OF MODALS TEACHING AND
LEARNING
73
IV.2 - SOME SUGGESTIONS IN TEACHING
MODALS
74
IV.2.1 - Explicate the context of the use
of modals
74
IV.2.2 - Explain the differences between
the types of meanings
75
IV.2.3 - Explain the differences between
the kinds of meanings
76
IV.2.4- Encourage the use of
modals
76
IV.2.5- Further suggestions
76
CONCLUSION
78
BIBLIOGRAPHY
80
APPENDIX I: FORMS OF MODALS
82
APPENDIX II: TESTS ON MODALS
85
APPENDIX III: CORRECTION OF THE TESTS
91
APPENDIX IV: PRACTICE
97
INTRODUCTION
This study deals with the deontic and epistemic uses of the
English modals in the writings of first year students of the department of
Anglophone Studies at the University of Ouagadougou. The deontic use refers to
modals expressing permission, advisability, necessity and obligation; whereas
the epistemic use refers to modals expressing possibility, probability, and
certainty.
Our interest in this study was aroused by our notice that the
first year students in the department of Anglophone Studies rarely use the
English modals in their speech; those who use some modals do so often
inappropriately. Why is that so? Do students master the deontic and epistemic
uses of English modals?
Many linguists and grammarians such as Leech, Wardhaugh, Celce
- Murcia and Larsen - Freeman implicitly disagree with the idea that students
master the meaning of modals since they claim that the meanings of modals are
almost incomprehensible, and even difficult to teach. Leech (1987:71) is very
aware of these difficulties as he asserts:
«Many pages, chapters, books have been written about the
modal
auxiliary verbs in English. What makes it so difficult to
account for
these words (which may be called «modal auxiliaries»
or «modals» for short)
is that their meaning has both a logical and a practical (or
pragmatic) element.»
Leech's view is shared by Wardhaugh (2003:56), who recognizes
that even if it is possible to make a distinction between the epistemic use and
the deontic use of modals, the distinction is not always clear in practice. He
sustains that «the modal verbs are complicated in the kinds of meanings
that they express».
Other grammarians sceptical about the correct use of modals by
learners are Celce-Murcia and Larsen- Freeman (1983:83). They worsen the
picture by placing the difficulties at teachers' level. Addressing their book
to teachers, they make this warning: «An additional problem in the
teaching of modals arises when you attempt to convey to your ESL/EFL students
the meaning of modals, periphrastic modals, and modal-like forms». If
teachers have problems to convey their EFL students the meaning of modals, no
one would logically expect from students to handle the use of modals, because
modals have both deontic meanings and epistemic meanings.
Do students of first year of the department of Anglophone
Studies at the University of Ouagadougou make any difference between the
epistemic uses and the deontic uses of modals? That is the question we shall
try to answer in this piece of research.
We shall assume that all the students we shall test are
English as a Foreign Language learners, that they attended all the course of
English at secondary school, and that they will answer our questions fairly. We
hypothesize that students will misuse modals and misunderstand their meanings,
because modals convey both deontic meanings and epistemic meanings, which they
are not clearly aware of.
We shall clarify the meaning of modals and then, test students
through written exercises to know whether the hypothesis should be confirmed or
invalidated.
Our research questions are the following:
- How well do students understand the meanings of modals?
- How appropriately do they use them?
- What is their modality tendency?
Our work is divided into four chapters. The first chapter
deals with the review of literature on pragmatics and modality in order to
present modals in their linguistic milieu. The second chapter is about the
research methodology, that is, how we collected and processed our data. The
third chapter displays the finding from our data analysis. The last chapter
provides some suggestions which, hopefully, may be useful for teachers, as they
could utilize them to improve their teaching of English modals for
communication, for students as they will be made aware of their strengths and
weaknesses in the use and understanding of English modals, and finally, for
researchers, because we intend through our piece of research to enlighten more
the issue of EFL learning.
CHAPTER ONE: THE REVIEW OF
LITERATURE
The purpose of this chapter is, firstly, to make an overview
of pragmatics as a linguistic science by giving its origin and historical
vagaries, its definition and that of some related key terms. Secondly, this
chapter explores definitions of modality and discusses the meanings of
modals.
I.1 - THE ORIGIN AND HISTORICAL
VAGARIES OF THE TERM «PRAGMATICS» ACCORDING TO LEVINSON (
1983)
Crystal (1996:301) recognizes that pragmatics is not easy to
define, for «no coherent pragmatic theory has been achieved because of the
variety of topics it has to account for». The term pragmatics is as vague
as Searle, Kiefer and Bierursh suggest in Levinson (1983:6)
«pragmatics is one of those words (societal and
cognitive are others) that give impression that something quite
specific and technical is being talked about when often in fact it has no clear
meaning». They say that pragmatics deals with all aspects of language use,
understanding and appropriateness.
The philosopher Charles Morris (1938:6) is reportedly1(*) said to be the
«father» of the term pragmatics in its modern usage.
He sought to establish a general shape of a science that studies signs:
semiotics. Morris divided semiotics into three branches: syntax, semantics and
pragmatics. He defines syntax as the study of «the formal relation of
signs to one another», semantics as the study of «the relation of
signs to the objects to which the signs are applicable», and pragmatics as
the study of «the relation of signs to interpreters». Each branch
consisted of pure studies, dealing
with the construction of the relevant metalanguage, and
descriptive studies, applying the metalanguage to the description of specific
signs and their usages.
It is the analytical philosopher and logician
Carnap who narrowed the scope of pragmatics to the study of the users of the
language. He explains the trichotomy of semiotics as follows:
« If in an investigation explicit reference is made to the
speaker,
or to put it in more general terms, to the user of the
language,
then we assign it [the investigation] to the field of pragmatics
...
If we abstract from the user of the language and analyze only
the expressions and their designate, we are in the field of
semantics.
And, finally, if we abstract from the designate also and analyze
only the
relations between the expressions, we are in (logical)
syntax.»
(Carnap, 1938:2 in Levinson,
1983:2-3)
Carnap's definition of pragmatics coincides with Morris's
(quoted in Levinson, 1983) descriptive semiotics, and Carnap finds a pure
pragmatics which he considered to deal with concepts like belief,
utterance and intention and their logical inter-relation.
Sayward (1974) quoted in Levinson (1983) noticed that Morris's
and Carnap's usages of the term pragmatics was ambiguous
because the particle «Oh» in English could be analyzed
pragmatically as well as semantically. Therefore, defining pragmatics as
«the study of aspects of language that required reference to the users of
language» will limit the scope of pragmatics to the study of indexical or
deictic words like the pronouns I and you, because in natural
language they are used to refer to the users of the language. Yet, it is this
definition that Montague (1968)2(*) developed.
To summarize, Morris defined pragmatics as the study of
psychological and sociological aspects involved in language, whereas Carnap
defined it as the study of concepts that make reference to users. But Montague
defined pragmatics as the study of deictic or indexical words; yet Anglo-
American linguistics and philosophy have a different sense, which we are
concerned with. Our next point is about the Anglo-American linguistics
definition of pragmatics.
I.2 - DEFINITION OF PRAGMATICS
Anglo-American linguistics and philosophy define pragmatics,
in its simplest terms, as the study of language use. But, this definition is
not satisfactory since language use embraces many parameters as various as each
of them deserves a particular field of study. The diversity of these fields
leads to miscellaneous definitions that we are going to look into now.
Levinson (1983) proposes some possible definitions of
pragmatics.
The lesser satisfactory (but possible) definition of
pragmatics is as follows: «Pragmatics is the study of those principles
that will account for why a certain set of sentences are anomalous». In
this sense, a sentence like «I am dead» would be incorrect because
there is no usual social context where someone would say «I am dead»,
for if I am dead I cannot say it. The definition is unsatisfactory because this
pragmatic anomaly is presupposed rather than explained.
Another unsatisfactory definition is: «Pragmatics is the
study of language from a functional perspective.» That definition includes
any aspect that contributes to the production of language, that is,
non-linguistic pressures and causes. It includes psycholinguistics, and
sociolinguistics; so it is too large.
A more limited scope of pragmatics needs to be set. A possible
definition might be, as Katz and Fodor quoted (in Levinson (1983))
«Pragmatics is concerned solely with performance principles of language
use». This definition implies that pragmatics is not concerned with the
description of linguistic structure but with the context of language use. It
does not refer to irony or understatement, where the context is quite opposed
to the use. The problem is that, if the definition wants to depart from the
description of linguistic structure, it will fail to analyze the aspects of
linguistic structure which directly encode features of the context.
Levinson (1983) states that any definition of pragmatics must
include the study of deixis, implicatures, presupposition and speech acts. He
defines pragmatics as «the study of deixis (at least in part),
implicature, presupposition, speech acts and aspects of discourse
structure». In fact, the definition unfolds the subject matter of
pragmatics.
McCarthy (1991:2) defines pragmatics as «the study of how
meaning is created in context». This means that, to understand the meaning
of an utterance one should refer to the context. It presupposes that the hearer
and the speaker are in the same context. Richards et al. (1985:225) give the
scope of pragmatics:
«Pragmatics
includes study of:
(a) how the interpretation and use of utterances
depend on knowledge of the real world
(b) how speakers use and understand speech acts
(c) how the structure of sentences is influenced by
the relationship between the speaker and the
hearer»
According to Cook (1989:157) pragmatics is «the study of
how the meaning of discourse is created in particular contexts for particular
senders and receivers». Discourse being the «stretches of language
perceived to be meaningful, unified and purposive» (P. 156), and context
being the «social and physical world which interacts with text to create
discourse». (P.156). Context includes the participants to discourse
production, the surroundings, the previous situation, etc..
In light of these definitions, pragmatics can be defined as
the study of language used in communication. That is, the study of language
which is concerned with the adaptation of symbolic expressions to the
referential, situational, actional and interpersonal context.
Our next point will deal with context.
I.3 - PRAGMATICS AND DISCOURSE
CONTEXT
The discourse analyst searches the relationship between
sentences in the same text whereas the pragmaticist wants to find out the
relationships between sentences and the real world. Some linguistic items
require contextual information. If, for example, a speaker says «I prefer
this table to that one», the hearer expects to see tables or he is aware
of the existence of tables. The words «I», «this», and
«that» used in the discourse refer to concrete existing things. These
terms are known as referring expressions. In pragmatics, some technical terms
such as reference, presupposition, implicature and inference are used to
explicate the relationships between the language users and the world in which
they live. Let us explain these terms.
I.3.1 - Pragmatic reference
Pragmatic reference is what Halliday and Hasan
(1976:31)3(*) call exophoric
reference. They say that exophoric references are forms which, «instead of
being interpreted semantically in their own right...make reference to something
else for their interpretation». The exophoric reference need not be
analyzed within the text - its interpretation lies outside the text - but
within the context of situation. So it refers to context. Levinson (1983:58)
defines context as a «set of pragmatic indices, co-ordinates or reference
points (as they are variously called) for speakers, and whatever else is
needed». When someone says, «Look at that» without any other
linguistic item, we expect him to point at something concrete. Example of
pragmatic or exophoric reference:
Look at that. (That =
)
(that refers to a pencil)
In the following sentence knowledge of the referred person is
necessary to understand the meaning of the modal.
E.g. He may leave.
The referring term is «He». If «He» refers
to someone of a higher social status than the speaker, the modal
«may» expresses a possibility; otherwise «may» will express
either possibility or permission.
I.3.2 - Pragmatic
presupposition
Pragmatic presupposition is well described in French by the
use of tu and vous. Levinson (1983:175) notes that the
presuppositions concerning the relationship holding between speaker and
addressee, expressed by the use of tu or vous, simply do not
affect «truth conditions». Thus, quoting Keenan (1971:51), Levinson
(1983:175) says that in «Tu es Napoléon» the use of
tu presupposes the addressee is socially inferior to the speaker or
personally intimate with the speaker». Keenan (1971) then, defines
pragmatic presuppositions as «a relation between a speaker and the
appropriateness of a sentence in context». In «Vous êtes
Napoléon», the use of vous shows a polite or a formal way
of talking to the addressee. All in all, the use of tu or
vous depends on the relationship between the addresser and the
addressee. When there is respect we use vous when there is less
respect we use tu.
In English, pronouns are not used to show when the request is
perceived more polite or less polite. The distinction is made through the use
of modals. Then an English native speaker would find «Could you give me
your pen?» more polite than «Can you give me your pen?». By
presupposing that the addressee is socially important, the speaker uses
«could» (a French speaker will use vous).
The meaning expressions that capture presuppositions are
called implicature expressions or conventional implicatures. What is
implicature?
I.3.3 - Implicature
The term «implicature» is used by Grice
(1975)4(*) to account for
what a speaker can imply, suggest, or mean, as distinct from what the speaker
literally says. In conversational implicature the speaker means more than what
he says.
For instance if a teacher says to his student: «You shall
not go out before I tell you», the student knows that «shall
not» expresses prohibition. He understands that if he trespasses, he will
be punished. So, the student will not do so. His attitude will be deferent if
the teacher says: «You may not go out before I tell you so». The
student will not be afraid to go out. By using «shall» instead of
«may», the teacher need not add: «If you go out, I shall punish
you». He makes economy of words.
I.3.4 - Inference
The term inference is used by Brown and Yule
(1983:256) to «describe that process which the reader (hearer) must go
through to get from the literal meaning of what is written (or said) to what
the writer (speaker) intended to convey». In fact, there is no concrete
relationship between what is heard or read and what is meant. It is the hearer
(reader) who establishes a connection between utterances and the context. In
this regard, references, presuppositions and implicatures are kinds of
inferences.
Inference is of paramount importance in the understanding of
the epistemic meaning of modals.
For instance, if A says, «The man may be there»; B
infers that A is not sure the man is there. The implicature is that the man may
not be there.
I.3.5 - Speech act theory
All the terms we have defined (reference, presupposition,
implicature) are used to indicate the relationship between discourse and
discourse context. Knowing the real world, the participants and their
expectations we can predict what they are likely to say and study the
relationship between what they say and what they think of their utterances. The
relation between the utterance and the speaker is studied within Speech Act
Theory.
Austin (1962)5(*) observes that some declarative sentences are not used
just to say things, i.e. describe states of affairs, but rather actively do
things. He suggests that the sentence «I declare you married» is not
simply asserting something but it is making something happened. Before the
sentence is pronounced you were a bachelor, but as soon as it is pronounced,
your matrimonial status has changed. Austin calls these kinds of sentences,
i.e. sentences used to make things happen, performatives.
Austin distinguishes two kinds of performatives: explicit
performatives and implicit performatives. In explicit performatives the speaker
avoids to be ambiguous by describing what he is performing. Hence, instead of
using some specific items like modals (as in «You must be back at ten
o'clock») or adverbs (as in «I shall be there without fail») the
speaker uses expressions like «I impose the obligation on you to be back
at ten o'clock» or like in «I promise Ishall be there».
On the contrary, in implicit performatives, short statements
are used, with specific grammatical devices. But many problems of
identification arise. For instance, how to know that «go» performs an
order or a daring or advice. This raises a context issue.
Austin identifies three basic senses in which when one is
saying something one is doing something and whereby three kinds of acts that
are simultaneously performed:
(i) «locutionary act: the utterance of a sentence with
determinate sense and reference
(ii) illocutionary act: the making of statement, offer,
promise, etc. in uttering a sentence, by virtue of the
conventional
force associated with it (or with it's explicit
performative paraphrase)
(iii) perlocutionary acts: the bringing about of effects on
the
audience by means of uttering the sentence, such effects
being special
to the circumstances of utterance.» (in Levinson,
1983:236)
Austin's illocutionary act has come to refer only to speech
act. In the example «Shoot her» Levinson (1983:236) comments,
«In appropriate circumstances, it had illocutionary force of variously,
ordering, urging, advising the addressee to shoot her; but the perlocutionary
effect of persuading, forcing, or frightening the addressee into shooting
her».
Austin's three kinds of acts that one can perform in speaking
are improved by Searle (1976)6(*). He lists five types of utterance:
(i) «representatives, which commit the speaker to the truth
of the
expressed proposition (paradigm cases: asserting,
concluding, etc.)
(ii) directives, which are attempts by the speaker to get the
addressee
to do something (paradigm cases: requesting,
questioning)
(iii) commissives, which commit the speaker to some future course
of
action (paradigm cases: promising, threatening,
offering)
(iv) expressives, which express a
psychological state (paradigm cases:
thanking, apologizing, welcoming, congratulating)
(v) declarations, which effect
immediate changes in the institutional state
of affairs and which tend to rely on elaborate
extra-linguistic institutions
(paradigm cases: excommunicating, declaring war, christening,
firing from employment)»
Searle's theory demonstrates that speech act deals with the
relation of the speaker to the utterance and specifically his attitudes towards
the utterance (asserting) or his commitment to the utterance (promising,
threatening). It also refers to the context of sentences especially to
participants, because depending on the addressee, «You can go»
expresses permission (if the addressee is of lower social status) or advice (if
the addressee is peer). In this regard, modals will be treated within speech
act. The relationship between speech and context needs a larger development. We
deal with it in our next section.
I.4 - THE CONTEXT OF SITUATION
According to Firth (1957) context of situation refers to the
different features that contribute to the production of discourse and make it
particular. To determine the context of a discourse, Brown and Yule (1983)
suggest that we should ask ourselves «what would be the discourse if the
context had been slightly different». The discourse may change if only one
feature changes.
Firth (1957: 182)7(*) declares:
«My view was, and still is, that `context of situation' is
best used
as a suitable schematic construct to apply to language
events...
A context of situation for linguistic work brings into
relation
the following categories:
A. The relevant features of participants: persons,
personalities.
(i) The verbal action of the participants.
(ii) The non-verbal action of the participants.
B. The relevant objects.
C. The effect of the verbal action»
Firth's study mentions the speaker and the addressee (their
speech and their gesture), the
purpose of the interaction, and the results of the
interaction. Firth's categories will be detailed by the ethnographer Hymes
(1964)8(*).
In his components of communicative events Hymes identifies:
- The addressor: the speaker or writer who produces the
utterance
- The addressee: the hearer or reader who is the recipient of
the utterance
- The audience: the overhearers or those who are not
addressed directly but they are part of the speaker context
- The topic: what is talked about, including what is
previously said and how things come sequentially.
The setting: the place and time where the event is situated.
It takes into account the physical relations of the interactants with respect
to posture and gesture and facial expression.
Knowledge of the addressee slightly influences the language
of the addressor. Thus, if you know the addressee is the president of the
Republic or the headmaster of a secondary school or your mother or your
classmate it is easier to predict the style or register you will choose to
address him. If the audience is political partners or students attending an
English course the language will be selected according to their expectations.
Knowledge of the context is essential to the use of modals. You would not say
to your teacher: «You must see a doctor» (obligation), when you mean
«You should see a doctor» (piece of advice).
I.5 - MODALITY
I.5.0 Introduction
The third edition of Oxford Advanced Learner's Dictionary
of Current English (1974) defines modality as «being modal»
(p.544) and modal as «relating to the mood of a verb» (P.544) It
defines mood as «one of the groups of forms that a verb may take to show
whether things are regarded as certain, possible, doubtful, etc. (p.548). These
definitions are defective for two reasons. Firstly, they don't distinguish mood
from modality; secondly, they confine modality to the only category of the
verbs. Moreover, the term «modality» is not defined as such, it
appeals us to refer to «modal». The term modality needs, therefore, a
specialized definition which can distinguish it from mood.
The terms «mood» and «modality» are so
linked that Palmer (1986:21) states that the distinction between mood and
modality is similar to that between tense and time, gender and sex. Yet, this
distinction will give some insight into the understanding of mood and modality.
Gender is to sex what modality is to mood. It then appears that, since gender
includes sex, breast, voice etc. modality includes moods and maybe other
things.
Jespersen (1924:313)9(*) restricts mood to a «syntactic not a notional
category, which is shown in the form of the verb». And Lyons
(1977:848)10(*) remarks
that «mood is a grammatical category that is found in some, but not all,
languages». If mood is a syntactic category and modality a notional
category, and if mood is not found as a grammatical category in all languages
whereas modality exists in all languages, we can infer that modality is not
expressed by mood in all languages. Consequently, mood is a grammatical
category and it is an element of modality while modality is a notional or
semantic category and as Palmer (1986) says, «the notion of modality is
much more vague and leaves open a number of possible definitions.»
Another distinction - though implicit - between mood and
modality is given by the sixth edition of the Oxford Advanced Learner's
Dictionary of Current English (2000:760). The dictionary does not have an
entry for the word «modality,» nevertheless it gives two grammatical
meanings to the term «mood».
The first definition is:
«Mood 4 [C] (grammar) any of the sets
of verb forms that shows whether what is said
or written is certain, possible, necessary, etc.»
The second definition is:
«Mood 5 [C] (grammar): one of the categories of verbs
use that expresses facts, orders, questions,
wishes or conditions: the indicative/imperative/subjunctive
mood.»
The first definition refers to modality and the second
definition is mood itself. How do linguists and philosophers define
modality?
I.5.1 - Defining modality
In modal logic, the branch of logic that deals with modality,
the term «modality» is not clearly defined. However, scholars
propose, implicitly or explicitly, some criteria for its definition. The
criteria we shall propose here are to be found in Palmer (1986). Basing his
discussion on Lyons (1977), Palmer identifies six criteria: proposition,
subjectivity, factuality, epistemic and deontic, possibility and necessity,
mood.
Jespersen (1924) and Lyons (1977) insist on the distinction
between proposition and modality. Proposition refers to the «contents of
the sentence» while modality refers to the «speaker's attitude or
opinion».
Rescher (1968:24-6)11(*) makes the distinction between proposition and
modality in the following way: «A proposition is presented by a complete,
self-contained statement which, taken as a whole, will be true or false: `The
cat is on the mat', for example». He goes on:
«When such a proposition is itself made subject to some
further
qualification of such a kind that the entire resulting complex
is
itself once again a proposition, then this qualification is
said to
represent a modality to which the original proposition is
subjected».
Hence, we have:
- The cat is on the mat (proposition)
- The cat may be on the mat (modality)
- Peter thought the cat was on the mat (modality)
Thus Rescher's definition of modality includes negation,
tense, aspect and clauses. Palmer concludes that it is «reasonable enough,
in a study of modality to consider not only the ways speakers express their
attitudes and opinions, but also the ways in which others may report their
expressions of them».
The second criterion in the definition of modality is
subjectivity. Lhérété and Ploton's (1990:132) explanation
of modality is worth noting:
«When someone speaks, he can
-whether try to be objective
-or try to be subjective
In the first case, the speaker relates the events as a
historian,
who has not participated in the achievement of these
events.
In the second case, the speaker/writer tells the
hearer/reader
how he perceives the events, through the filter of his
sensibility.
Modality is the use of this filtering by the
speaker/writer12(*)»
Subjectivity is then of paramount importance in modality.
Palmer (1986:16) suggests that modality is essentially subjective because
reference is made to the «speaker's opinion and attitude». He further
argues that modality could be defined as «the grammaticalization of
speaker's (subjective) attitudes and opinions». Thereby, the modal verb
«can» cannot be considered as modal when it expresses the subject's
ability - instead of the speaker's opinion. Palmer (1986:17) notes, «If
modality is concerned with the attitudes and opinions of the speaker,
subjectivity is clearly basic». Modality can then be expanded to adverbs
such as frankly, fortunately, possibly; verbs such as appear,
assume, think 13(*).
The third criterion in the definition of modality is set by
Lyons (1977)14(*). He
suggests that we should consider the commitment of the speaker to the
statement. Whenever the speaker commits himself to the truth of what he
asserts, there is no modality. For Lyons, «straight forward statements of
fact are non-modal» because there are propositions. He proposes some
examples:
«- He may have gone to Paris
- Perhaps he went to Paris
- It is possible that he went to Paris»
He notes that there is modality in the examples because they
contain a modal verb, a modal adverb and a modal adjective respectively.
The fourth criterion to be considered is the epistemic and
deontic interpretations of modals. Most scholars agree that there are two types
of modality. Jespersen (1924:320-1) 15(*)recognizes two sets of modality: modality `containing
an element of will' and `not containing an element of will'. These sets
correspond to Lyons' (1977:452)16(*) reference to `the speaker's opinion or attitude
towards the proposition that the sentence expresses or the situation that the
proposition describes'. Von Wright (1977:93)17(*) uses `epistemic modality' versus `deontic modality'
whereas Hofmann (1966)18(*) used `epistemic modality' and `root modality'.
Celce-Murcia and Larsen-Freeman (1983:83) use the terms `logical probability
use' and `social interactional use' of modals. In this work we shall use Von
Wright's terms. The following examples illustrate the different types of
modality and interpretation between brackets.
Epistemic interpretation:
He may come tomorrow. (Perhaps he will)
Deontic interpretation:
He may come tomorrow. (He is permitted)
The fifth criterion is possibility and necessity. Palmer
(1986:20) notes, «Where epistemic and deontic modality are so clearly
linked, the link depends upon possibility and necessity». Quoting Lyons
(1977:787), he says that possibility and necessity are «the central
notions of traditional modal logic». He argues that they are logically
related in terms of negation, and this account for the fact that cannot
as an expression of negative possibility appears to function as the
negative of epistemic must.
The issue lies on the use of may and must.
Let us consider the sentences:
(a) Epistemic:
He may be there. (possibility)
He may not be there. (it is possible that he is there)
He can't be there. (it is not possible that he is there)
(b) Deontic:
He must be there. (necessity)
He can't be there. (it is necessary that `he is not there')
He may not be there. (it is not necessary that `he is
there')
Palmer (1986) remarks that in (a) may not corresponds
to `possible' and cannot corresponds to `not possible' while in (b)
cannot equates to `necessary' and may not corresponds to `not
necessary'. He notes that in (a), may not expresses a positive fact
and cannot a negative one whereas in (b) it is the reverse. To
enlighten this point let's group the utterances:
Epistemic: He may not be there Deontic: He may not
be there
It is then clear that epistemic and deontic modalities are
linked in negation.
The last criterion for the definition of modality is the
distinction between mood and modality. Mood is a grammatical category whereas
modality is a notional or semantic category. Mood is an element of
modality19(*). All
criteria considered, we admit that the English modal auxiliaries appertain to
modality.
Although some criteria are set to determine when an utterance
is modalized, and though modality is not only made by grammatical devices but
also by lexical items, McCarthy (1991:84) remarks that modality is often
thought of as the province of the closed class of modal verb and treated as
part of grammar of English. This account for the definitions English grammar
books give to modality.
Wardhaugh (2003:56) writes, «Modality refers to the
possible world in which the state or event denoted by the verb is situated: the
kinds of truth, possibility, necessity, etc. that must exit there. The modal
verbs are can, may, will, shall and must». As for
Huddleston (1984:165), modality is «a rather broad term for the kind of
meaning characteristically expressed by modals». He interchangeably uses
`modals', `modal auxiliary verbs' and `modal auxiliaries'. These authors limit
modality to modals.
Another grammar book which has the same viewpoint is the one
by Feigenbaum (1985:115). The introduction to modals is as follows:
«Time, status, and relevance are used to respect what
happened,
what is going to happen, etc. In addition to these three types
o
f information, it is possible to express an attitude or
evaluation
of a situation. For example we can indicate that an action is
probable or that it is contrary-to-fact; we can indicate that
there is permission or an obligation to do something.
Modal auxiliaries and phrases are used in order to give the
speaker's or writer's point of view about a situation.»
Feigenbaum's `speaker's or writer's point of view about a
situation' coincides with Lyons' (1977:452)20(*) `speaker's opinion or attitude towards the
proposition' in his definition of modality. The most daring definition which
confines modality to modal verbs is that of Wardhaugh (2003:275) in the
glossary. It states that modality is «the meaning expressed by a modal
verb». How does modality come to be confined to modals? To know this, let
us look into modals.
I.5.2 - Forms and uses of
modals
Modals are a type of auxiliary verbs used to indicate an
attitude about an action or a state. Most modals can be used when discussing
the present, past or future meanings.
There are five basic or central modals: CAN, MAY, MUST, SHALL,
WILL. The verbs NEED, DARE, OUGHT (TO) are also sometimes classified as modals,
because of some of the characteristics they share with the modals above.
Modals have specific properties and diverse meanings. We shall
present first the grammatical forms of modals and then discuss their
meanings.
I.5.2.1 - The
grammatical forms of English modals
Modals have some grammatical properties they share with the
auxiliary verbs BE and HAVE. Huddleston (1976:333) quoted in Palmer (1986),
calls them the NICE properties = modals occurrence with Negation, Inversion,
`Code' and Emphatic affirmation as in:
I cannot go.
Must I come?
He can swim and so can she.
He will be there.
Beside these properties, modals have distinctive
properties.21(*)
In English there are three lexical forms of modals: one-word
modals, periphrastic modals and modal-like forms.
One-word modals
Historically present tense forms Historically past tense
form
can could
will would
may might
shall should
must /
Central modals and their periphrastic modal counterparts
central modal periphrastic modal
can to be able to, to be likely to, to
be allowed to
will to be going to, to be
about to, to be apt to
must to have to, to have got to
should ought to, to be to, to be
supposed to
would (= past habit) used to
may to be permitted to
Modal-like forms
had better
would rather
would prefer
would like
NEED and DARE are used sometimes as modal auxiliaries and
sometimes as main verbs.
There are plenty of modals with several forms, nevertheless
their properties can be easily learned by a diligent student. Would it be the
same with the meaning of modals? Let us discuss the meanings of modals.
Most scholars agree that each English modal verb has two
uses22(*): the deontic use
and the epistemic use. We shall present first, the deontic use of modals, and
then their epistemic use. Finally, we shall compare the two uses.
I.5.2.2 - Deontic use of modals
The term `deontic' is used in the study of modals to include
them in the set of modality Jespersen (1924:320)23(*) characterizes as
«containing an element of will». Jespersen's list of deontic uses is
as follows:
«containing an element of will
jussive go (command)
compulsive he has to go
obligative he ought to go/we should go
advisory you should go
precative go please
hortative let us go
permissive you may go, if you like
optative (realizable) may he still be alive
desiderative (unrealizable) would he were still alive
intentional in order that he may go»
A close look at the compulsive, obligative, advisory
and permissive shows that they contain a modal verb, and they
express some interaction between the speaker and the hearer. Specifically, the
speaker is addressing someone, using a kind of authority. Deontic modality in
this sense seems to be directives or commissives in
accordance with Searle's study of speech act. Searle (1979:14)24(*) defines commissives as
«where we commit ourselves to do something» and directives as
«where we try to get our hearer to do something» (Searle,
1983:166)25(*). It is
remarkable that both are subjective (they are about the intention of the
speaker) as well as performative (they are about things to perform). For that
reason, they will always express future actions. Palmer (1986:97) notes,
«At the time of speaking a speaker can get others to act or commit himself
to action only in the future». By using directives or commissives the
speaker may be giving permission, advice, or he may be imposing obligation or
warning of necessity. We shall discuss these elements separately.
I.5.2.2.1 - Request
Not only can speaker express his own attitudes but he can also
ask the addressee about his - whether he considers an action deontically
permissible or necessary. He does it through request.
E.g. May I come in?
Must I come in?
The use of the interrogative form with the possibility modal
may is a request for permission. Thus, May I come in? does
not mean `Is it the case that I have permission to come in?' but it means `I
ask you to give me the permission to come in'. Conversely the use of must
is essentially a request for information alone. Must I come in?
would never be a request for the hearer to place an obligation upon the speaker
(Wardhaugh, 2003).
Shall I come in? does not ask for permission or for
information, but it is a request for advice involving the first person. In this
way, shall is a consultative, and it can be replaced by
should:
Shall I call her or will you? Should I call her?
SHALL can be used to express invitation; in this case,
should cannot substitute for shall without changing the
meaning.
Shall we meet tonight? Should we meet tonight?
(would you like to meet me tonight?), (is it advisable
that we meet tonight?),
i.e., an invitation i.e., a question
In addition to the use of questions for invitation, modals
are used for requests.
WILL, WOULD, CAN, and COULD are used for general request with
`you' as in:
WILL
CAN you help me with this job?
WOULD
COULD
Can and will in making request seem to
imply: is this possible...? While could and would seem to
query the willingness of the person being addressed. Could and
would are more formal.
MAY, MIGHT, CAN, COULD are used in request for permission.
`I/we' are used. In deontic modality, may and can are
interchangeable, which is not the case in epistemic modality.
Example: May/Can
Might I go now?
Could
Might and could are less direct.
Leech(1987:89) notes that Shall I/we is favoured by
politeness because «it is more polite to consult the wishes of the
listener, than to assert one's own wishes as speaker». In request the
`authority figure' is the hearer.
Krupp and Tenuta (2002) remark that with modals of
invitation you ask someone to go someplace or to do something with you, while
with modals of request you ask someone else to do something for you or to grant
you the permission to do something. Between equals, asking permission is like
making a request. Thus, «Can I take your pen?» is almost the same as
«Can you let me take your pen?»
Since the speaker can ask for permission, the listener can
grant permission.
I.5.2.2.2 - Permission
The distinction between general request and request for
permission becomes clear when statements are expressed:
Yes, I can. * Yes, I could.
Answers to general requests
Yes, I will. * Yes, I would.
Yes, you may. * Yes, you might.
Answers to request for permission
Yes, you can. * Yes, you could.
It follows that may and can are used to
give permission.
Feigenbaum (1985:118) notes that very conservative grammar
books maintain that only may expresses permission; however
can is common in many situations except in the most formal ones. Can
is traditionally considered less polite and less `correct' than
may.
By using may or can the speaker is qualified
to grant permission. When the speaker says, «You may go now» he means
that he gives the permission to go, but he cannot predict whether the hearer
will go.
Wardhaugh (2003:57) signals that some language users think
that Can I open the window? does not mean Do I have your
permission? because can must be epistemic in this use (do I have
the ability) not deontic. Only the context says the meaning of the modal.
Compare:
He may leave. (now that he has answered my question)
He can speak English. (Because he has my permission to do
so)
Palmer (1986:103) notes that with can the speaker is
dissociating himself from the permission, whereas he is associating with it in
using may. Examples:
You may smoke here. (You have my permission)
You can smoke here. (It is allowed to smoke)
MAY and CAN have the past tense form MIGHT and COULD but MIGHT
is very rarely used at all to indicate past time. By saying, «You could
come» the speaker means the subject was permitted to come yet when he says
«You might come» might does not express past time but a
strong force than may. Huddleston (1984:170) asserts that substituting
may for might in the past is a special use of
might.
COULD can be used to answer to a general request but it
expresses conditional.
E.g. - Could you help me with this job?
- Yes, I could (if you would wait a few minutes while
I finish this work)
Besides the fact that the speaker can allow someone to do
something, he can undertake the decision by himself through advice.
I.5.2.2.3 - Advisability
According to Lhéhéré and Ploton (1990),
SHOULD, OUGHT TO are used to give advice or recommendation. The results may not
be bad if the advice is not taken. The listener may or may not take the advice,
i.e., the speaker thinks that the obligation may not be fulfilled.
Should is more often used than ought to. The use of
should implies that a certain behavior characterizes the subject. In
«Your wife should write you letters», the speaker thinks that the
wife does not write enough. He recommends her to do so. The use of ought
to implies that the circumstances should bring the subject to have a
definite behavior, it is not unfortunately the case. In «Your wife ought
to write you letters», the speaker thinks that it is normal, and natural
that a wife writes letters to her husband.
Stronger advice can be expressed by the use of HAD BETTER. If
the advice is not taken the result may be bad for the listener. It is almost an
obligation.
E.g. You had better shut the door. (If you do not want me to
beat you)
Should and ought to are also used
to talk about beliefs and opinions. In these cases, there is no recommendation
or advice.
E.g. You should marry her if you want to be happy.
(Advice)
People should get married if they want to be happy.
(Personal opinion)
Sometimes the listener may not have the choice. Then, there is
a necessity.
I.5.2.2.4 - Necessity
Necessity is stronger than advisability. There is no feeling
of choice whether to do something or not. MUST is a common way of indicating
necessity. (Wardhaugh, 2003)
E.g. He must do it. (Or we are lost).
In necessity and advisability the speaker does not speak as
holding an authority but he speaks as a member of society: the speaker believes
it is a social duty for him to advise; advice can also come from the love the
speaker has for the addressee.
E.g. You must see a doctor, father.
NEED also is used to express necessity as in «You need to
see a doctor, father».
If the speaker thinks the listener will not respect his
advice, he can impose upon him his intention by using authority. It becomes an
obligation.
I.5.2.2.5 - Obligation
Obligation is often expressed by Searle's (1983:166)
commissives. SHALL with 2nd and 3rd person form expresses
obligation.
E.g. You shall go to school.
James shall have money next week.
You will go to school (whether you like it or not: it
is quasi - imperative)
The speaker commits himself to ensuring that the event takes
place: he promises to arrange that the person addressed will go to school and
that James will receive the money.
Modals of obligation are also used for something a person is
required or obliged to do because of laws, customs, rules or circumstances.
When the source of obligation is not the speaker we use HAVE TO. There may be a
penalty or consequences for not fulfilling the obligation.
E.g. Applicants must have post graduate qualifications.
He must obey his master.
(Compulsion)
He has to obey his master. (This is the
rule)
With have to the speaker is dissociating himself from
the obligation. It is objective because the obligation tends to come from a
source outside the speaker. The usual implication of must as an
obligation is that the speaker is the person who exerts authority over the
person(s) mentioned in the clause, i.e., the source of obligation is the
speaker. This calls for pragmatic presupposition since a person from an
inferior social rank cannot compulse his superior to do something. Moreover,
the implicature of «You shall go to school» is that, «If you do
not go to school I shall punish you».
Therefore, a deep analysis of deontic modality requires the
study of implicature, presupposition and speech act for many reasons. Firstly,
within speech act there are commissives and directives whereby permission is
given or obligation is imposed. Secondly, through implicature advice can be
taken or not, something judged necessary or not. Finally, for an obligation to
be fulfilled or a permission to be granted, there is the presupposition of the
speaker's authority over the listener. Thence, if a boy says, «Dad, you
must go to school» it will be interpreted as a necessity. But if the
father says, «John, you must go to school» it will be interpreted as
an obligation; such an interpretation depends on the social relationship
between the speaker and the hearer, and the necessity of the advice. It is
possible to order the modals according to the speaker's degree of authority
and/or conviction, or the urgency of the advice.
100 Obligation
Necessity
Advisability
Permission
0 Request
Speaker's authority or urgency of the message
increases, but not necessarily in equal increments.
Applications of utterances to the scale:
100 You will see a doctor
You shall see a doctor
You must see a doctor
You need to see a doctor
You had better see a doctor
You should see a doctor
You ought to see a doctor
You might/could see a doctor
You can/may see a doctor
0 May I see a doctor?
Summary of deontic use of modals:
Request: could, can, would, will, may, must, shall,
should
Invitation: shall, would, can, could
Permission: may, could, can, might
Advisability: should
Necessity: must
Obligation: must, shall, will
Students need to know the degrees of the deontic use of modals
and be able to use modals that are deontically appropriate. For Celce-Murcia
and Larsen-Freeman (1983:84), «many ESL/EFL students, even at the advanced
level, do not recognize that they are often perceived by native speakers of
English as being abrupt and aggressive with their requests». They suggest
that if we could teach them to soften their requests by employing the
historical past-tense forms of the modals, they might find their request being
better received.
I.5.2.3 - Epistemic use
of modals
The term `epistemic' should apply not simply to modals that
basically involve the notion of possibility and necessity, but to any modal
that indicates the degree of commitment by the speaker to what he says. The
term `epistemic' etymologically comes from Greek and means `understanding' or
`knowledge'. It should be interpreted as showing the status of the speaker's
understanding our knowledge. This includes the speaker's own judgments, his
beliefs and the kind of warrant he has for what he says. Palmer (1986:54)
believes that the purpose of epistemic modals is to provide an indication of
the degree of commitment of the speaker. He says that the speaker «offers
a piece of information, but qualifies its validity for him in terms of the type
of evidence he has». Epistemic modals bear subjectivity in that they
indicate the status of the proposition in terms of the speaker's commitment to
it. Wardhaugh (2003:56) states, «If it is a statement, the proposition in
sentence containing an epistemic modal may be true or false, and if it is not a
statement, the proposition it expresses may also be true or false».
E.g. He may go tomorrow. (Or he may not- I am not sure)
Would he agree? (Or not?)
Jespersen (1924:321) quoted in Palmer (1986:10) defines
epistemic modality as «containing no element of will». The speaker
does not assert his will but states what he thinks of a situation on the basis
of what he knows or sees. Jespersen provides a list of epistemic uses of
modals:
«- Containing no element of will
Apodictive twice two must be (is necessarily) four
Necessitive he must be rich/or he could not spend so
much
Assertive he is rich
Presumptive he is probably rich/he would (will) know
Dubitative he may be (is perhaps) rich
Potential he can speak
Conditional if he is rich
Hypothetical if he were rich
Concessional though he is rich»
Though the assertive, the conditional, the hypothetical
and the concessional express modality in its broad sense, we cannot
consider them in the current study because they do not contain modal
auxiliaries. By contrast, the apodictive, the necessitive, the presumptive
and the dubitative contain modals and they express the commitment of the
speaker to the utterance, because the speaker infers or predicts, from what he
knows, the probable state of facts. The potential corresponds to
Palmer's dynamic modal. In deontic modality, the speaker tells how he wants
things to happen while in epistemic modality the speaker tells how he thinks
things are or will be. Inference is the basis of epistemic modality. The
speaker uses the epistemic modals to indicate how sure he is that an action or
situation takes place, will take place, or took place. Sureness can be low
(possibility), high (probability), or 100% (certainty).
I.5.2.3.1 - Possibility
Modals of possibility are used to refer to an intention that
is not definite at the time of speaking. CAN, COULD, MAY, and MIGHT are used
for present and future situations. Could and might show a
less strong possibility than can and may. May does
not occur in questions to express possibility. Example of possibility:
It may be true. (= `it is possible that it is true')
Leech (1987:81) notes that, in general, may
represents `factual possibility', and can represents `theoretical
possibility'. He provides two sets of equivalent statements:
FACTUAL: the road may be blocked
= `it is possible that the road is
blocked'
= `perhaps the road is blocked'
THEORETICAL: the road can be blocked
= `it is possible for the road to be
blocked'
= `it is possible to block the road'
He comments that «the road can be blocked» describes
a theoretical conceivable happening, whereas «the road may be
blocked» feels more immediate, because the actual likelihood of an event's
taking place is being considered. Leech concludes that «factual
possibility» is stronger than «theoretical possibility». Then,
may is stronger than can. The scale of possibility is as
follows (decreasingly):
The illness may be fatal.
The illness can be fatal.
The illness might be fatal.
The illness could be fatal.
While possibility is about something that is 50%certain to
happen, probability is something that is very certain of occurring if one
considers the evidence. It may not occur, but it probably will.
I.5.2.3.2 - Probability
Something is probable when it is expected. Modals of
probability indicate a conclusion or deduction, an evaluation based on earlier
information. SHOULD and OUGHT TO are used to express probability. Ought
to is normally stressed, whereas should is not so. (Leech,
1987:82)
E.g. They should be waiting for her.
They ought to be waiting for her.
MUST is used to express inference. This is a conclusion based
on specific evidence or information. It is more certain than expectation.
E.g. Someone is knocking at the door. I was expecting to
receive Mary. So the person knocking must be Mary.
Must is stronger than ought to because
ought to is based on assumptions while must relies on known
facts.
E.g. A lazy student might say, «I remember that the
teacher has repeated this rule over, and over again; I shall no longer study
other rule, the test must be about this rule». A more cautious student
will say, «The test ought to be about this rule».
A possible scale of probability:
Must
Ought to
Should
With ought to the speaker lacks confidence in what he
says, with must the speaker has confidence in what he says. If he is
more than confident in what he says he will use straightforwards statement, but
as the action does not yet occur, the speaker uses modals of certainty.
I.5.2.3.3 - Certainty
Modals of certainty indicate a prediction, agreement, or
promise. WILL (and sometimes SHALL with I or we) is used for
present and future statements of prediction, agreement, or promise.
(Feigenbaum, 1985)
Will is used for prediction when the speaker makes a
`forecast about the present' concerning an event not directly observable. For
instance when someone says, «That will be Dick. I was expecting him to
call me. [On hearing the telephone ring]. In this case must can
replace will, but with a weaker force.
The prediction can be based on the force of `typical or
characteristic behavior'. This is common in general statements, whether of a
proverbial, scientific or some other kind. Accidents will happen could
be paraphrased as, «It is a predictable or characteristic fact about life
that accidents happen».
Will is also used for future time promise. I will
meet you at nine o'clock could be paraphrased: «Do not worry; I will
come, I promise».
SHALL (with I/we) is used for emphatic certainty. In
the example, «Unless you die, I shall meet you again», shall
expresses more than just a prediction; it is a very strong insistence of my
invitation to meet you again.
Emphatic certainty:
Normal Emphasized
Will.............shall
Shall............. Will
A possible scale of certainty (decreasing):
Will emphasized
shall
shall normal
will
must
The study of epistemic modals shows how a speaker can move
from simple supposition to assertion. The following examples display the degree
of certainty. The degree are not equidistant.
100% Will It will rain tomorrow
Must It must rain tomorrow
Should It should rain tomorrow
May It may rain tomorrow
Could It might rain tomorrow
Might
O% Negation It will not rain tomorrow
(This scale of prediction is adapted from Celce-Murcia and
Larsen-Freeman: 1983:87)
The prediction or inference can be weak
(could/might), stronger (may), strong (should), very
strong (must), or absolutely certain (will).
It is noteworthy that epistemic modals have corresponding
adverbs and adjectives:
Could/might------possibly, possible
May---------------perhaps, quite possible
Should------------probably, probable
Must--------------certainly, certain
Will---------------undoubtedly, undoubted
Now that we have stated the inner differences between
epistemic modals, we can contrast them with deontic ones.
I.5.2.4 - Epistemic use versus deontic use of
modals
Though both epistemic and deontic uses are expressed in a
single modal, there may be differences between them. To interpret a modalized
utterance some parameters should be considered.
The first thing to determine is the intention of the speaker.
If the speaker thinks that the person involved in the utterance is more or less
free to act or to be, he will put emphasis on the subject. In this case we deal
with deontic modality.
Subject Modality Predicate
Speaker
Deontic Modality
E.g. He may come tomorrow
= He is permitted to come
He must be in his office
= He is obliged to be in his office
If the speaker believes that he can more or less predict the
occurrence of events or state of facts, he will put focus on the predicate.
Here we are within epistemic modality.
Subject Modality Predicate
Speaker
Epistemic Modality
E.g. He may come tomorrow
= Perhaps he will
He must be in his office
= I am certain that he is
We can provide a chart of the five central modals in terms of
deontic and epistemic use regarding the speaker's intention.
CHART 1: The speaker's
intention through the use of modals
SPEAKER'S POINT OF VIEW
|
ABOUT A CHARACTER MORE OR LESS SPECIFIC TO THE SUBJECT
(DEONTIC)
|
ABOUT THE CHANCES OF OCCURRENCE OF THE ACTION (EPISTEMIC)
|
Inherent character (genetic)
e.g. Boys will be boys
|
will
|
Absolutely certain occurrence
e.g. It will rain tomorrow
|
Character conferred on the subject by an authority
(authorization)
e.g. Every citizen can change their name
|
Can
|
Possible occurrence but not certain
e.g. Accidents can happen
|
Character conferred on the subject by the speaker
(permission)
e.g. You may go out
|
May
|
Quite possible occurrence
e.g. They may win the match
|
Character imposed on the subject by the speaker
e.g. You shall go to school
|
Shall
|
Strong insistence on occurrence
e.g. Justice shall be rendered
|
Recall of an obligation that the speaker would like to see
performed
e.g. They must come on time
|
must
|
Deduction of a certain occurrence by the speaker
e.g. He must be tired
|
This chart is adapted from Lhérété and
Ploton (1990:133)
Lhérété and Ploton note that with
must, the speaker is concerned with the link between the subject and
the predicate by considering both: no one is favored.
Subject Predicate
MUST
Speaker
The second difference between epistemic and deontic uses of a
modal lies on the use of paraphrase. Adverbs and adjectives can often be used
to paraphrase the epistemic but not the deontic use of a modal26(*).
The third distinction between the epistemic and the deontic
use can be made by using periphrastic modals.
CHART 2: Modal auxiliaries and periphrastic
modals
MODAL
|
EPISTEMIC
|
DEONTIC
|
Will
Can
May
Shall
Must
|
To be about to
To be likely to
To be liable to
To be bound to
To be sure to
|
To be apt to
To be permitted to
To be allowed to
To be to
To be obliged to
|
Time also can be used to distinguish the deontic use from the
epistemic use of a modal. With deontic modality the time involved in the idea
of the speaker is future: the speaker requires or permits something to be done
after the obligation is imposed or the permission is granted.
E.g. You must do your homework. (From now on)
They may leave. (They can start going)
With the epistemic modality, by contrast, the time involved in
the speaker's idea is generally present or past.
E.g. The teacher must be sick. (Present)
He must have overeaten. (Past)
Another criterion which might differentiate the two types of
modalities is the identities of participants. Depending on the social status of
the participants, we may be dealing with the epistemic or deontic use of a
modal.
E.g. A teacher to his student:
- You may meet me next Monday. (deontic use of
may)
(= I allow you to meet me)
A student to his teacher:
- You may meet me next Monday. (Epistemic use of
may)
(= it is possible that we meet)
To summarize, a distinction of the epistemic use from the
deontic use of a modal might be made by considering the chart below.
CHART 3: Distinctive features of
meanings
DISTINCTIVE FEATURES
|
EPISTEMIC
|
DEONTIC
|
Speaker's subject is of
|
higher social status
|
lower social status
|
Speaker's action orientation (time)
|
present or past
|
Future
|
Speaker focuses intention on
|
predicate
|
Subject
|
Paraphrase
|
adverbs and adjectives
|
past participle
|
Periphrastic equivalence
|
(see chart above)
|
(see chart above)
|
Speaker's point of view is
|
based on knowledge or beliefs or opinion
|
about acts to be performed
|
This chart is valid only for the central modals in the present
tense. The reader might notice that we did not discuss forms such as past,
conditionals and negation. We want to deal, in this work, with the simplest
forms, with hope to undertake further studies on the complex forms. With past
tense or with negation, the meanings of modals do not follow the framework of
our discussion. The reader may also remark that we dealt only with differences.
We focus on differences between the epistemic use and the deontic use of modals
because we want to know whether students perceive this distinction. It does not
mean that there are no similarities. We can note en passant that they have
common criteria which make them modals.
Modality is broadly defined as the use of words that carry
important information about the stance and attitude of the sender to the
message. These words can be verbs, adverbs, or adjectives. However, many
grammarians reduced modality to the set of verbs (will, shall, can, may, must)
known as modals. This is certainly due to the fact that the study of modality
reveals two large types of modality: epistemic modality and deontic modality.
The English modals seem to be the only words that express both senses. Modals
have particular grammatical properties, and each modal has semantically
intricate meanings. However, a pragmatic approach can help state the
differences between these meanings.
CONCLUSION
Pragmatics is the study of how to interpret the meaning of an
utterance depending on context. Any pragmatic study requires the analysis of
some key terms (reference, presupposition, implicature, speech act, and
inference) which show the relations of participants to discourse. Indeed, it is
the context that shapes the meaning of words; however, the speaker's intention
can affect his utterances so that the study of these utterances could
demonstrate how far the speaker is committed to his utterance. The appearance
of the attitude and the stance of the speaker towards the proposition is known
as modality. In English, modality is often limited to the set of modals because
they are the only words that have the criteria of double-meaning epistemic and
deontic. At first sight, the epistemic and the deontic senses overlaps since a
single modal conveys both meanings. A deeper analysis proves the existence of
distinctive features of the epistemic and the deontic uses. Having in mind
these criteria the student can not only know whether a modal is appropriate but
also he can use it appropriately. The issue is to find out whether students
bear these features in mind when interpreting the meaning of a modal or when
using a modal. To solve the problem, we must test students but, how to
undertake this test so that the recognition and the production of a modal in an
appropriate situation will reflect students' knowledge and understanding of
modals? The following chapter will provide the research methodology.
CHAPTER TWO: RESEARCH
METHODOLOGY
In this chapter we shall describe our research methodology.
For this, we shall divide the chapter into five sections: the approach, the
data collection techniques and instruments, the sampling, the problems
encountered in the field and solutions provided, and the data analysis
procedure.
II.1 - APPROACH
The main objective of our study is to find out how well first
year students at the department of Anglophone Studies, understand and make use
of English modals. That is, how well they use modals in appropriate contexts.
Do they consistently use the right modal in the right context? Do they
understand the meaning of modals?
Our hypothesis is that students don't always understand the
meanings of modals and that they do not always use modals appropriately because
modals express both deontic and epistemic meanings. The modals we shall study
are: must, may, should, will, shall, can, might, could and would.
We will check our hypothesis in the production and
comprehension of a sample of students. To test this hypothesis, two concepts
should be considered: production and understanding. By production, we mean the
use of modals through writing; Understanding refers to the capacity to
recognize the meaning of modals in written sentences. (cf. section II.2). The
appropriate use and the understanding of modals depend on the knowledge of the
speaker's subject (Who the speaker is and of whom he is speaking), his action
orientation (The speaker is talking about the state of facts or he is talking
about something that should be performed), the focus of his intention (The
speaker is drawing attention on a subject or on an event), the basis of his
point of view (The speaker's point of view rests on known facts or on
forthcoming facts), the periphrastic equivalence of the modals, and the
paraphrase of the modals (An adjective or adverb is convenient, or a past
participle).
A piece of research including all these points requires the
adoption of a pragmatic approach, since they would be well displayed through
the study of reference (speaker, addressee, subject), presupposition (social
status), implicature (knowledge of the speaker's action orientation); inference
( knowledge of the speaker's evidence) and speech act (representatives,
performatives). We used a quantitative approach to determine how many students
understand the meanings of modals and how many students use modals
appropriately. We used specific techniques and instruments to collect our data.
II.2 - DATA COLLECTION TECHNIQUES
AND INSTRUMENTS
As research instrument, we used written tests. The
identification cards were designed to discover the students. In the cards we
wanted to identify the gender of the testee and check also if he/she is a
newcomer. The second aspect is important for us because we aimed at assessing
the level of students just coming from secondary schools. We were interested in
the gender because we wanted to know the rate of participation of girls in the
test.
To go into the study proper, we followed Katz's (1977:19)
proposition quoted in Levinson (1983) stating that a pragmatic theory is part
of performance because pragmatic theories explicate the reasoning of speakers
and hearers in working out the correlation in a context with a token
proposition. We used the written test as the performance item.
The written test was preferable to the oral test because the
data collection was easier and quicker. In fact, a prior informal observation
of students' spoken data had allowed us to notice that they are almost bare of
modals. In addition, students' understanding of the modals used in some
interviews was more difficult to check. We thought the solution was in written
test. We made a pretest to see if the test would be adapted to the level of
students. The pretestees made some suggestions and we made the final test.
We utilized two modal understanding /production tests of
forty sentences, each test made of three series of exercises. The first test
embodying twenty sentences was designed to assess the students' understanding
of modals. We proposed the context wherein we used the modal and we asked the
students to find the pragmatic meaning in a multiple choice format.
The first series, made of seven sentences, was about the
deontic meaning of modals; the second series, composed of three sentences, was
about the epistemic meaning of modals; and the third series, containing ten
sentences, was a combination of deontic or/ and epistemic meaning. The
contexts were made clear enough to avoid confusion of meanings, except in the
third series where we intentionally left two sentences without clear contexts.
By doing so, we wanted to assess the students' modality tendency. (cf. Appendix
II)
In the second test we used twenty sentences. We utilized a gap
filling test where we asked the students to fill in the blank with the
appropriate modal verb. In this test also divided into three series, the first
series had seven sentences and was about the deontic meaning of modals; the
second series, with three sentences, dealt with the epistemic meaning of
modals; and the third series had ten sentences and was a combination of deontic
and epistemic meanings.
In each series, we proposed a list of modals and gave a
context where a modal should be used. We ask the students to give the right
modal referring to the pragmatic meaning of the modal indicated in front. The
context was so that only one right modal was appropriate. To assess the
students' modality tendency we left two sentences without contexts but with two
meanings and we arranged that only one modal expressed both the deontic and the
epistemic meanings.
In both tests, we used miscellaneous meanings and modals to
display the differences between the deontic and the epistemic meanings, and the
inner differences between modals within each type of meaning. (cf. Appendix
II)
All the sentences were formulated taking into account the
distinctive features of the meanings of modals.
We asked the students to fill in the identification cards
before dealing with the test. The session lasted more than two hours and the
following section describes our sampling.
II.3 - SAMPLING
To select the sample, we enquired about the exact number of
first year students at the Anglophone Studies Department. The registry staff
gave us a total number of 1,135 students, who constituted our population. The
research took place in an amphitheatre at a period when the students were
supposed officially to have course. We chose this place and that time because
we wanted to ensure that the students tested were from the English department
and that they were in first year.
Powell and Connaway (2004:90) sustain that the most
straightforward type of survey research is descriptive, and it is designed to
ensure that the sample is reasonably representative of the population to which
the researcher wishes to generalize, and that the relevant characteristics have
been accurately measured. Suggesting that Simple Random Sample (S.R.S.) being
used for survey research, they note that Systematic Sample, which is a Simple
Random Sample is considered by most researchers to be reliable and accurate. We
used a systematic sample, a technique that involves taking every nth
element from a list until the total list has been sampled. It enhances
the likelihood of every element to be selected. We used the S.R.S. technique by
taking every 10th student from one row to the other until the three
rows were sampled and the sample size completed. By taking every
10th student our sample size should be made of 113 students, which
should correspond to 10 per cent of our total population. Unfortunately, we
ultimately got 64 testees.
This piece of research was not done without difficulties on
the ground; nevertheless, some solutions were found.
II.4 - PROBLEMS ENCOUNTERED IN THE
FIELD AND SOLUTIONS PROVIDED
During the administration of the test we encountered some
major problems from the beginning to the end.
One of the problems we encountered is that students were not
very disciplined, and we could see some students working in group. We told them
many times not to work in group and explain to them what could be the
consequences of group work in the results of our study. Some students stopped
working in group but some did not.
Another problem is time limitation. We wanted to administer
the test in two hours, but, as there were not so many students taking the test,
we did not want to discourage the few volunteers who were doing the exercises.
So, instead of two hours, we gave students all the time they needed. They
worked until they rendered their papers without any time constraint.
The third problem is relative to the number of the testees. In
addition to the fact that we did not have the 113 volunteers for the test,
among the 80 papers we dealt, only 62 gave back their papers. We wanted to have
at all cost the sample we needed. So, the following day, we went back to the
class and asked students to bring the copies they had about them. No one
reacted. Whereupon, we gave another opportunity to students to take the test.
We asked if there were volunteers to sit the test. Only two students accepted
to be tested. That is the reason why we had 64 tested instead of 113 as we
wished.
Last but not least, the class was noisy but there was nothing
we could do to stop the noise and enable students to think deeply to do the
test.
At the end of the test some students suggested to write their
names on their papers, which we accepted as they wanted to see their marks
later. Moreover, the students suggested to see the correction of the test, what
we accepted on the spot.
After solving the problems and getting the adjusted data, we
analyzed the data step by step.
II.5 - DATA ANALYSIS PROCEDURE
We analyzed first the identification cards of the 64 testees
to classify them into repeaters and newcomers groups. Then we analyzed the test
of the 62 newcomers by starting with the recognition of the meaning of modals.
We assumed that it would be easier for the students to recognize the meaning of
modals than to produce them. So we wanted to move from the simple elements to
the complex ones.
We dealt with the identification cards, the recognition of the
meaning of modals and the production of the meanings of modals separately in
order to categorize them for a statistical analysis. Powell and Connaway
(2004:232) says that statistical analysis can indicate how many persons,
objects, scores, or whatever achieved each value (or fell into each category)
for every variable that was measured. These calculations known as frequency
distributions were usually reported in tables. The reported elements were
followed by some comments or interpretations. The results are presented in the
following chapter.
CHAPTER THREE: FINDINGS
FROM OUR DATA ANALYSIS
In this chapter we shall present the different results we got
from the data we collected. We shall present first the identification items;
then, the tests properly; and finally, some probable sources of misuses and
misunderstandings.
III.1 - FINDINGS FROM THE
IDENTIFICATION ITEMS
Among the 80 papers we gave to students only 64 did the
exercises and gave the papers back. We may think that those who brought the
papers home were not able to do the tests. There are not different from those
who refused to take the papers though the exercises had been explained. Among
the 1,135 students that compose the class only 64 accepted to try our test.
They represent 5.63 % of the class. The percentage is low, that tends to show
that students avoid modals. That is the reason why they use them rarely in the
compound of the university; thence, the difficulties to have natural data with
them.
When we analyzed the identification citems, we discovered that
there were 49 boys, including 2 repeaters; and 15 girls, all newcomers.
Repeaters did not take profusely the test because they may have thought that
they already knew the modals; which is not obvious as a test on them needs to
be done to know if they do better than newcomers in modals.
As we were not concerned with the use of modals by repeaters
or with a comparative
study between repeaters and newcomers, we did not analyze the
papers of the 2 repeaters.
If we consider the participation of boys and that of girls we
remark that boys participated
more than girls. In fact, the rate of participation of boys,
regarding their number in the class, is 7.31% while that of girls is 3.22 %
since the class is composed of 670 boys and 465 girls. In this regard, we might
think that girls are more reluctant to be tested on modals than boys; that is,
girls avoid modals more than boys do. This can explain why girls did not want
to react to modals when we were attempting to have natural data of the use of
modals by first year students. We did not analyze the data separately because
we did not want to do a comparative study between boys and girls performances.
We made a common analysis of data.
III.2 - FINDINGS FROM
THE EXPERIMENT
In this section we shall present the different results we got
from the data collected. We shall present first the recognition of the meaning
of modals, then the production of modals and ultimately we shall draw some
conclusions and verify our hypothesis.
III.2.1 - Meaning Recognition
In the first test we wanted to know which meaning students
would give to the modals proposed in sentences.
The results on scores, the distribution of meanings to modals,
the confusions between types of meanings, the confusion between kinds of
meanings and the students' modality tendency are presented.
III.2.1.1 - Scores and
comments
III.2.1.1.1- Scores of the deontic meaning
recognition and
comments
The first part was scored out of seven and was about the
deontic meaning of modals. Here are the different marks with the number of
students.
Chart 4: Scores of the deontic meaning
recognition
MARKS
|
NUMBER OF STUDENTS
|
0
|
0
|
1
|
5
|
2
|
12
|
3
|
14
|
|
|
4
|
12
|
5
|
12
|
6
|
5
|
7
|
2
|
On the left of the chart there are marks and on the right
there are the numbers of students who get these marks. For example, five (5)
students get the mark one out of seven (1/7). The students who get the average,
that is, more than four out of seven (4/7) are separated from those who don't
get it. So, thirty-one (31) students out of sixty two get the average. This
number corresponds to fifty per cent (50%) of the testees. Half of the testees
recognize the right meanings and half of them fail to recognize the appropriate
meanings within the deontic meaning. 2 students get 7/7.
III.2.1.1.2 - Scores of the epistemic meaning
recognition and
comments
The second part dealt with the epistemic meanings. It was
scored out of three. The results are as follows:
Chart 5: Scores of the epistemic meaning
recognition
MARKS
|
NUMBER OF STUDENTS
|
0
|
10
|
1
|
28
|
|
|
2
|
8
|
3
|
16
|
In this part thirty-eight (38) students don't get the average
but twenty-four
(24) do. This makes respectively 61.29 % and 38.70 %. In this
regard, we can say that most of the testees don't know the epistemic meanings.
Though 16 students get 3/3, 10 students get 0/3.
III.2.1.1.3 - Scores of the deontic or/and
epistemic meaning recognition and comments
Part three was a combination of the deontic meaning and the
epistemic one. There were four sentences in each kind of meaning. The following
chart displays the marks with the number of students corresponding to them.
Chart 6: - Scores of the deontic or/and
epistemic meaning recognition and comments
MARKS
|
NUMBER OF STUDENTS
|
0
|
0
|
1
|
1
|
2
|
10
|
3
|
16
|
4
|
|
|
|
5
|
12
|
6
|
11
|
7
|
6
|
8
|
4
|
9
|
1
|
10
|
1
|
By combining the two types of meanings, 56.45 % of the testees
get the average, opposed to 46.54 %, those who don't get the average (27/62 and
35/62). 1 student gets 10/10 while the lowest mark is 1/10.
III.2.1.1.4 - Scores of the test on recognition and
comments
The test one aimed at finding how many students could
recognize the meanings of modals. The answer is as follows:
Chart 7: Scores of test on
recognition
MARKS
|
NUMBER OF STUDENTS
|
0
|
0
|
1
|
0
|
2
|
0
|
3
|
0
|
4
|
1
|
5
|
1
|
6
|
2
|
7
|
5
|
8
|
8
|
9
|
12
|
|
|
10
|
10
|
11
|
8
|
12
|
5
|
13
|
1
|
14
|
4
|
15
|
2
|
16
|
1
|
17
|
1
|
18
|
1
|
19
|
0
|
20
|
0
|
In the test on recognition, in general, 33 students out of 62
get the average while 29 get less than 10 out of 20; this is respectively 53.22
% and 46.77 %. More than half of the testees get the average, they recognize
the right meanings. The best mark is 18/20 and the lowest is 4/20.
III.2.1.1.5 - Comments on scores
When scores are analyzed, it appears that students do better
in deontic meanings (50%) than in epistemic meanings (38.70 %). When the two
meanings are mixed up, students do better (56.45 %). The last performance may
be due to the fact that some students, who have not got the right meaning in
the first two parts, get the right meaning in the third part. In part one 50%
of students got the average; logically, in part three less than 50% of students
were expected to get the average (44.35 %). The result is reverse as 56.45 % of
students have the average in part three. There is an increase of 12.10 %. We
may conclude that 12.10 % find the right meanings by chance. After having
analyzed students' marks we shall analyze the answers to the exercise.
III.2.1.2 - Distribution of meanings to
modals
By asking students to find the right meanings for the modals
proposed we wanted to know if they would give the right meaning to the modal.
We notice that every student attributes at least one wrong meaning to a modal
and every meaning was attributed at least one wrong modal. These wrong meanings
attributed to modals appear in the following chart. From left to right there
are meanings attributed to modals wrongly; from up to down there are the
different modals. The box «nothing» is used for the sentences not
filled by students. The modals «could» and «would» were not
used in our test. At the intersection of modals and wrong meanings there are
the numbers of students who used ithem and their percentages in comparison to
the total number of students. For example, 6 students wrongly think that WILL
expresses General Request, that is 9.67 % of the testees think so.
CHART 8: Distribution of meanings to
modals
WRONG
MEANING
MODAL
|
GENERAL REQUEST
|
ASKING FOR PERMISSION
|
INVITATION
|
GIVING PERMISSION
|
ADVISABILITY
|
NECESSITY
|
OBLIGATION
|
POSSIBILITY
|
PROBABILITY
|
CERTAINTY
|
NOTHING
|
CAN
|
2
03.22%
|
|
4
6.45 %
|
|
|
|
|
|
3
4.83%
|
5
8.06%
|
|
WILL
|
6
09.67%
|
1
01.61%
|
2
03.22%
|
|
4
06.45%
|
14
22.58%
|
1
01.61%
|
17
27.41%
|
20
32.25%
|
1919
30.64%
|
3
4.83%
|
MAY
|
16
25.30%
|
8
12.92%
|
7
11.29%
|
15
24.19%
|
7
11.29%
|
3
4.83%
|
4
6.45%
|
3
4.83%
|
36
58.06%
|
1
1.61%
|
1
1.61%
|
SHALL
|
11
17.74%
|
8
12.92%
|
6
9.67%
|
6
9.67%
|
4
6.45%
|
15
24.19%
|
1
1.61%
|
1
1.61%
|
2
3.22%
|
|
1
1.61%
|
MUST
|
3
4.83%
|
25
40.32%
|
4
6.45%
|
5
8.06%
|
7
11.29%
|
17
27.41
|
46
74.19%
|
11
17.74%
|
1
1.61%
|
20
32.25%
|
3
4.83%
|
MIGHT
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
1
1.61%
|
|
32
51.61%
|
10
16.12%
|
|
SHOULD
|
4
6.45%
|
1
1.81%
|
5
8.06%
|
1
1.61%
|
5
8.06%
|
11
17.74%
|
9
14.51%
|
29
46.77%
|
4
6.45%
|
18
29.03%
|
4
6.45%
|
According to the above chart, 74.19 % of students wrongly
attribute Obligation to MUST; that is, whenever they see MUST they
think of obligation. This can be due to the fact that they are taught that MUST
expresses Obligation. They do not know that MUST can express something else
according to the addressor. Most of them think so in the sentence «You
must see a doctor, father». Students focus on what they are taught than to
reality. «Father» is the addressee, the speaker is probably a child.
Morally speaking, a child cannot oblige his father to do whatsoever. 58.06 %
of students wrongly believe that MAY expresses probability while
51.61% wrongly say that MIGHT expresses probability. The results show
that the meanings of modals are ignored. We have classified modals from the
least known to the best known in the following chart, derivated from the above
chart.
In the chart below, we use the term «case» to
qualify the number of wrong meanings attributed to the modal. For example,
there are 4 meanings wrongly used for «can» (general request,
invitation, probability and certainty). So there are 4 cases. The term
«uses» refers to the number of times wrong meanings are attributed to
modals. The uses of «can» are 14 [(2general request) + (4 invitation)
+ (3 probability) + (5 certainty) = (14 uses)]. It is the horizontal line that
is considered.
CHART 9: Frequency of distribution
|
MUST
|
MAY
|
SHOULD
|
WILL
|
SHALL
|
CAN
|
MIGHT
|
CASES
|
11
|
11
|
11
|
10
|
10
|
4
|
2
|
USES
|
142
|
102
|
91
|
87
|
55
|
14
|
43
|
The least known modal is MUST because it is used in 11 cases
or situations, and 142 times. The above chart does not include the results of
the sentences number one and number four of part three as these sentences
contain two meanings at the same time. We constructed them so because we wanted
to identify students' modality tendency through them. It's the reason why we
did not say their meanings.
III.2.1.3 - Students'
modality tendency
We purposely left two sentences without contexts for the
students to give the meanings according to their perception. The modals being
ambiguous, each student interprets them.
CHART 10: Modality tendency
MEANING
MODALS
|
DEONTIC
MEANING
|
EPISTEMIC
MEANING
|
SOMETHING
ELSE
|
NOTHING
|
MUST
|
56
90.32%
|
5
8.06%
|
1
1.61%
|
|
CAN
|
11
17.74%
|
45
72.58%
|
5
8.06%
|
1
1.61%
|
As students were given the choice between the epistemic
meaning and the deontic
meaning, 90.32 % of students preferred the deontic meaning
with MUST, and 8.06 % of students opted for the epistemic meaning with MUST.
72.58 % of students chose the epistemic meaning for CAN whereas 17.74 % of the
students chose the deontic meaning. Averagely 40.32 % of students preferred the
epistemic meaning while 54.03 % had a deontic tendency. So, students' modality
tendency is the deontic meaning.
Regarding the percentage, we can say that the percentage of
the deontic meaning with MUST may be linked to students' perception of
obligation since most of them believe that MUST always expresses
obligation. As for the high percentage of CAN with the epistemic
meaning students may be confusing possibility with ability.
Furthermore, the high percentage of the deontic meaning over the epistemic may
be related to the fact that students have social values that conditioned them
to have social tendency. Psychologically, students may be giving little
importance to logic as logic is the basis of epistemic meanings. They may not
be very futuristic by projecting events; they may lack entrepreneurial flair.
The tendency may also be due to the confusion of meanings. In the following
point, we shall verify whether they make differences between meanings.
III.2.1.4 - Confusion
between the kinds of meanings
By «kinds of meanings» we mean the different
meanings modals express such as «obligation, possibility». To find
whether students make differences between modals, we use a chart on which there
are expected meanings from students, and the meanings students attributed
wrongly to modals. We use here the methods used for chart 8.
Chart 11: Confusion between the kinds of
meanings
WRONG
MEANING
EXPECTED
MEANING
|
GENERAL REQUEST
|
INVITATION
|
GIVING
PERMISSION
|
ASKING FOR
PERMISSION
|
ADVISABILITY
|
NECESSITY
|
OBLIGATION
|
POSSIBILITY
|
PROBABILITY
|
CERTAINTY
|
NOTHING
|
GENERAL
REQUEST
|
|
2
3.22%
|
5
8.06%
|
23
37.09%
|
|
13
20.96%
|
11
17.74%
|
|
|
|
1
1.61%
|
INVITATION
|
9
14.51%
|
|
3
4.83%
|
8
12.92%
|
1
1.61%
|
1
1.61%
|
|
1
1.61%
|
2
3.22%
|
|
|
GIVING PERMISSION
|
6
9.67%
|
7
11.29%
|
|
2
3.22%
|
2
3.22%
|
2
3.22%
|
3
4.83%
|
2
3.22%
|
1
1.61%
|
|
1
1.61%
|
ASKING FOR PERMISSION
|
10
16.12%
|
3
4.83%
|
11
17.74%
|
|
4
6.45%1
1.61%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
ADVISABILITY
|
3
4.83%
|
5
8.06%
|
1
1.61%
|
1
1.61%
|
|
11
17.74%
|
9
14.51%
|
2
3.22%
|
3
4.83%
|
3
4.83%
|
2
3.22%
|
NECESSITY
|
1
1.61%
|
|
|
|
6
9.67%
|
|
44
70.96%
|
|
|
|
1
1.61%
|
OBLIGATION
|
5
8.06%
|
7
11.29%
|
4
6.45%
|
1
1.61%
|
8
12.92%
|
30
48.32%
|
|
2
3.22%
|
3
4.83%
|
20
32.25%
|
2
3.22%
|
POSSIBILITY
|
|
1
1.61%
|
6
9.67%
|
3
4.83%
|
2
3.22%
|
|
1
1.61%
|
|
47
75.8%
|
15
24.19%
|
|
PROBABILITY
|
2
3.22%
|
1
1.61%
|
|
|
4
6.45%
|
3
4.33%
|
12
19.35%
|
34
54.83%
|
|
34
54.83%
|
3
4.83%
|
CERTAINTY
|
3
4.83%
|
1
1.63%
|
|
|
1
1.63%
|
3
4.83%
|
1
1.61%
|
13
20.96%
|
18
29.03%
|
|
3
4.83%
|
DEONTIC OR
EPISTEMIC
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
1
1.61%
|
In the chart we observe that students confuse meanings. Many
meanings are confused with others: 75.80 % of students wrongly use
probability for possibility; 70.96 % of students confuse
obligation with necessity; 54,83 % of students confuse
possibility with probability; certainty with
probability.
Students' confusion between probability and
possibility may be due to their misunderstanding of these meanings or
to their thinking systems. Indeed, if they don't know the meanings they cannot
use them appropriately. However, there may be some psychological attitudes that
urge them to think that what is possible is probable. They are confusing,
someway, theory and practice as possibility is linked to theory and probability
to facts. Students may be dealing in their everyday life with theories; they
may not be realistic enough. Is this phenomenon due to the social context or to
the teaching and learning system? Further research needs to be done in this
sense.
If we analyze the students' answers under a psychological
viewpoint, we may say that most of them fear the authority. That is, they are
still under the control of some authority. They don't have the freedom of acts.
70.96 % of them think that what is necessary is obligatory. Which is not true
for someone who can resist and disobey to what other people think is
obligatory. What is necessary is not necessarily obligatory.
Students confuse kinds of meanings, and the most confused
meaning is supposed to be the least known. The board below ranks them by using
the term cases and uses as for the chart 9.
Chart 12: Frequency of confusion of the kinds
of meanings
|
OBLIGATION
|
ADVISABILITY
|
GIVING PERMISSION
|
PROBABILITY
|
CERTAINTY
|
POSSIBILITY
|
INVITATION
|
GENERAL REQUEST
|
ASKING FOR PERMISSION
|
NECESSITY
|
BOTH
|
CASES
|
10
|
10
|
9
|
8
|
8
|
7
|
7
|
6
|
5
|
4
|
1
|
USES
|
82
|
40
|
26
|
93
|
42
|
75
|
25
|
55
|
29
|
52
|
1
|
By «both,» we mean «the epistemic meaning and
the deontic meaning». Students seem to ignore deeply obligation. Instead
of saying obligation, they use the other meanings. 10 other meanings are
proposed instead of obligation, and this, 82 times. Then come advisability
(10cases, 40 uses) and giving permission (9 cases, 26 uses). The kinds of
meanings more confused are deontic. In the following section we shall analyze
the confusions between the epistemic meaning and the deontic meaning.
III.2.1.5 - Confusion
between the types of meanings
By «types of meanings» we mean the deontic meaning
and the epistemic meaning. Our interest in this point is to find out how much
students confuse the two meanings: how many students use the deontic meaning
wrongly for the epistemic meaning and vice versa. The analysis of the data
leads us to the following chart.
Chart 13: Confusion between types of the
meanings.
WRONG
MEANING
EXPECTED
MEANING
|
EPISTEMIC MEANING
|
DEONTIC MEANING
|
NOTHING
|
EPISTEMIC MEANING
|
|
27
43.54 %
|
34
6.45 %
|
DEONTIC MEANING
|
33
53.22 %
|
|
3
4.83 %
|
The chart shows that 53.22 % of students wrongly use the
epistemic meaning for the deontic meaning and 43.54 % do the reverse. 11.29 %
of students do not make up their minds. This result proves that students are
deontic-based since most of them (53.22 %) attribute the epistemic meaning to
the deontic one. That is, besides the deontic meanings use rightly they think
some epistemic meanings are also deontic. This chart also witnesses the
miscellaneous confusions within the deontic meaning. The epistemic meaning may
be less confused because it is not well known: the phenomenon of avoidance.
After having studied the different confusions students have,
we shall give an overall comment on test one.
III.2.1.6 - Comments on
recognition
A glance at recognition reveals that students have a low
understanding of the meanings of modals regarding the hair-raising confusions
they make about the meanings of modals.
If the average level of the sample is calculated, the
students' level is under average with the epistemic meaning (part two of the
test), 1.48/3; and fairly good with the deontic meaning (part one of the test),
3.59/7. Their level is fairly good when meanings are combined (part three of
the test), 5.06/10; thereon the level in the test about the recognition of the
meanings of modals is fairly good (test one), 10.09/20.
The level of students is not null, but they make some
confusions that bring us think that they use the meanings randomly and
thoughtlessly. For example, according to the chart 5, 40.32 % of students say
that MUST expresses asking for permission and 6.45 % say that MAY
expresses obligation, while 17.74 % confuse asking for
permission and giving permission.
Those who don't want to make such mistakes leave some blanks.
Thence, there were twelve (12) blanks in test one; that is, 19.35% of students
leave blanks. Those who leave the blanks may be applying the language learning
strategy of avoidance. They can be therefore ranked in the group of those who
did not take the test.
The recognition of modals seems not to be easy for students.
We shall analyze their production in the next point.
III.2.2 - Modal Production
We wanted to know how appropriately students could use the
modals. First of all, we shall present the results and comment them; and then,
we shall make some comments on production.
We shall present scores and comments, the distribution of
modals to meanings, the confusions between modals, the use of modals to express
ambiguity, and the students' preference of modals.
III.2.2.1 - Scores and
comments
III.2.2.1.1 - Scores of the deontic meaning
production and comments
Part four was designed to assess the use of modals to express
the deontic meanings. It was scored out of seven. The scores and comments
follow:
Chart 14: Scores of the deontic meaning
production and comments
MARKS
|
NUMBER OF STUDENTS
|
0
|
0
|
1
|
3
|
2
|
9
|
3
|
14
|
|
|
4
|
14
|
5
|
17
|
6
|
4
|
7
|
1
|
One student scores 7/7 while 3 students
score 1/7. The chart shows that 36 students get the average whereas 26 fail to
have it. The numbers give respectively 58.06 % and 41.93 %. More than half of
students get the average in the production of modals to express deontic
meanings. What is the case of the epistemic meanings?
III.2.2.1.2 - Scores of the epistemic meaning
production and comments
This part was about the epistemic meanings; it was scored out
of three. The scores follow:
Chart 15: Scores of the epistemic meaning
production
MARKS
|
NUMBER OF STUDENTS
|
0
|
9
|
1
|
31
|
|
|
2
|
21
|
3
|
1
|
40 students fail to get more than 1.5 out of 3 in this part
while 22 do. That is, 35.48 % succeed in this part, against 64.51%. There is
more failure than success in the production of modals to express the epistemic
meanings. Only 1 student gets 3/3 whereas 9 students scores 0/3.
III.2.2.1.3 - Scores of
the deontic or/and epistemic meaning production
and
comments
Students were given all the meanings - the deontic meaning
and the epistemic meaning - and they had to use modals to express them. This
part was scored out of 10. The scores are presented in a chart.
Chart 16: Scores of the deontic or/and
epistemic meaning production
MARKS
|
NUMBER OF STUDENTS
|
0
|
1
|
1
|
2
|
2
|
8
|
3
|
15
|
4
|
13
|
|
|
5
|
8
|
6
|
13
|
7
|
2
|
8
|
0
|
9
|
0
|
10
|
0
|
1 student has 0 out of 10; the best mark is
7 out of 10 and 2 students have got it.
39 students failed to get the average whereas 23 students took
the part successfully. The percentage of success is 37.09% and that of failure
is 62.90%. More than half of students fail in this part, where meanings are
mixed. Let's now analyze the test one in general.
III.2.2.1.4 - Scores of
the test on production and comments
The test number two aimed at finding how well students can
produce modal verbs appropriately in say contexts. The analysis of data gives
the following results.
Chart 17: Scores of the test on
production
MARKS
|
NUMBER OF STUDENTS
|
0
|
0
|
1
|
0
|
2
|
0
|
3
|
2
|
4
|
0
|
5
|
4
|
6
|
4
|
7
|
7
|
8
|
8
|
9
|
10
|
|
|
10
|
10
|
11
|
7
|
12
|
3
|
13
|
6
|
14
|
1
|
15
|
|
16
|
|
17
|
|
18
|
|
19
|
|
20
|
|
The chart shows that 2 students got 3 out of
20 and 1 student got the best mark of 14 out of 20. 35 students missed the
average whereas 27 passed the test. Only 43.54 % of students succeeded in
production of modals while 56.45 % failed. In all, there is more failure than
success.
III.2.2.1.5 - Partial conclusion on scores of
production
When all the scores of production are considered in terms of
failure, the epistemic use of modals has the highest percentage (64.51 %). It
means that the use of the epistemic modals is the least known domain of
students. If we compare the two meanings it appears that students do better in
the deontic use of modals (58.06 % of success) than in the epistemic use (35.48
% of success). In the sixth part, where the uses are mixed, the degree of
success is 37.09 %. In fact, the combination of the deontic meaning and the
epistemic one should give, logically, 46.99 % of success in part six. But it is
not so in part six as the percentage of success is 37.09 %. There is a decrease
of 9.9 %. This means that 9.9 % of students found some of the right modals in
the preceding parts but they failed in the part six. We are allowed to say that
they have found the right modals by chance, or they failed in using the right
modals by chance. At all account, modals are used haphazardly.
III.2.2.2 -
Distribution of modals to meanings
In our attempt to assess students' use of the modal verbs we
proposed the ideas and ask them to use modals to express them. Each student
used modals to express the ideas. Sometimes the right modal is used and
sometimes, the wrong modal is used.
Chart 18: Distribution of modals to
meanings
WRONG
MODAL
MEANING
|
CAN
|
WILL
|
SHALL
|
MAY
|
MUST
|
COULD
|
WOULD
|
MIGHT
|
SHOULD
|
NOTHING
|
INVITATION
|
8
12.92%
|
2
3.22%
|
|
1
1.61%
|
|
9
14.51%
|
6
9.67%
|
5
8.06%
|
3
4.83%
|
|
GIVING PERMISSION
|
4
6.45%
|
14
22.58%
|
4
6.45%
|
18
29.03%
|
4
6.45%
|
9
14.51%
|
4
6.45%
|
13
20.96%
|
6
9.67%
|
2
3.22%
|
ADVISABILITY
|
2
3.22%
|
8
12.92%
|
3
4.83%
|
5
8.06%
|
19
30.64%
|
34.83%
|
10
16.12%
|
8
12.92%
|
|
3
4.83%
|
NECESSITY
|
5
8.06%
|
8
3.22%
|
9
14.51%
|
2
3.22%
|
|
|
3
4.83%
|
11
17.74%
|
23
37.09%
|
2
3.22%
|
OBLIGATION
|
|
|
|
1
1.61%
|
54
87.09%
|
|
2
3.22%
|
|
15
24.19%
|
|
GENERAL
REQUEST
|
18
29.03%
|
4
6.45%
|
2
3.22%
|
14
22.58%
|
|
17
27.41%
|
5
8.06%
|
5
8.06%
|
5
8.06%
|
6
9.67%
|
ASKING FOR PERMISSION
|
|
1
1.61%
|
2
3.22%
|
|
|
|
|
|
2
3.22%
|
|
POSSIBILITY
|
13
20.96%
|
4
6.45%
|
5
8.06%
|
5
8.06%
|
7
11.29%
|
8
12.92
|
5
8.06%
|
5
8.06%
|
1
1.61%
|
4
6.45%
|
PROBABILITY
|
7
11.29%
|
14
22.58%
|
3
4.83%
|
17
27.41%
|
1
1.61%
|
19
30.64%
|
7
11.29%
|
13
20.96%
|
4
6.45%
|
4
6.45%
|
CERTAINTY
|
5
8.06%
|
|
2
3.22%
|
4
6.45%
|
10
16.10%
|
3
4.83%
|
5
8.06%
|
7
11.29%
|
6
9.67%3
|
3
4.83%
|
BOTH
|
6
9.67%
|
6
9.67%
|
|
12
19.35%
|
2
3.22%
|
12
19.35
|
|
6
9.67%
|
8
12.92%
|
2
3.22%
|
54 students out of 62, that is 87.09% of students wrongly
used WILL. Either they don't know that WILL expresses obligation or
they don't take into account the context, or they do think obligation
is expressed only by MUST. In the sentence «You will go to war or my name
is not Captain Blood» the context is situated in a wartime. So, the
speaker, who is authoritative, will oblige certainly a soldier to go to war. It
is imperative. Here, the testees underlook the context of situation (wartime),
the addressor (a captain) and the addressee (a soldier, presupposed). Students
failed to infer the addressee. Moreover, 37.09 % of students used SHOULD to
express necessity when they should use MUST. By using SHOULD it may
appear a piece of advice instead of a necessity. So, they fail to transmit the
right idea. In the sentence, «Honey, you are sick, you must take these
tablets to feel well» the lover is not advising, he is implicitly saying
«if you don't take these tablets you will not feel better or you will
die». The testees did not perceive this implicature. Besides, some
students failed to use modals to express say ambiguity. For instance, 12
students used MAY to express both obligation and probability whereas 8 students
used SHOULD to express both permission and possibility.
Furthermore, we wanted to know the least known meaning. We
counted the number of modals attributed wrongly to meanings, and the number of
times wrong modals were used to express each meaning. We ranked them in
decreasing order in the following chart.
Chart 19: Frequency of distribution of modals
to meanings
|
PROBABILITY
|
GIVING
PERMISSION
|
POSSIBILITY
|
GENERAL REQUEST
|
ADVISABILITY
|
CERTAINTY
|
NECESSITY
|
BOTH
|
INVITATION
|
OBLIGATION
|
ASKING FOR PERMISSION
|
CASES
|
10
|
10
|
10
|
9
|
9
|
9
|
8
|
8
|
7
|
4
|
3
|
USES
|
89
|
78
|
57
|
76
|
61
|
45
|
57
|
54
|
34
|
72
|
5
|
The chart displays that probability is the meaning to
which students give wrong modals the most. The 9 modals plus «blanks»
are used to express probability and happens 89 times. By «both» we
mean the deontic meaning and the epistemic meaning. Students could not use a
simple modal to express the two meanings at the same time (8 cases and 54
times). The following section is about the wrong use of modals to express
ambiguous meanings.
III.2.2.3 - Use of
modals to express ambiguity
In the test, one sentence was given with two meanings
(possibility or giving permission) and another sentence with
the meanings (obligation or probability). We aimed at finding
out how far students perceive the ambiguity of meanings and the difficulties to
use a single modal to express both meanings. By determining the rates of
ambiguity of modals we shall know if they are aware of the ambiguous meanings
of modals. Apparently, very few are not aware of this ambiguity. The chart
below shows the results.
Chart 20: Ambiguous use of modals
WRONG
MODAL
AMBIGUOUS
MEANINGS
|
CAN
|
WILL
|
COULD
|
WOULD
|
MIGHT
|
SHOULD
|
SHALL
|
MAY
|
MUST
|
NOTHING
|
POSSIBILITY OR
PERMISSION
|
1
1.61%
|
5
8.06%
|
7
11.29%
|
|
1
1.61%
|
4
6.45%
|
|
|
2
3.22%
|
1
1.61%
|
OBLIGATION
OR PROBABILITY
|
5
8.06%
|
1
1.61%
|
5
8.06%
|
|
5
8.06%
|
4
6.45%
|
|
12
19.35%
|
|
1
1.61%
|
19.35 % of students think that MAY expresses the ambiguity
between obligation and probability. No student uses would or
shall. We shall study the cases and uses.
Chart 21: Frequency of ambiguity
|
OBLIGATION OR PROBABILITY
|
POSSIBILITY OR PERMISSION
|
CASES
|
7
|
7
|
USES
|
33
|
8
|
The use of modals to express both obligation and
probability seems more difficult (7 cases, 33 uses) than that of
possibility or permission.
To use one modal to express both meanings is easier (7 cases)
than to use one modal to express specific meaning (10 cases, cf. chart 12).
The fact that students used wrong modals to express meanings
or the ideas suggested in the test may be due to the confusions they make about
modals.
III.2.2.4 - Confusion
between modals
Many students confuse meanings. They use one modal to express
a given meaning instead of using the appropriate modal. When the appropriate
modal is not used, the meaning of the sentence or the idea suggested is changed
into another idea, or into delirious meaning. For instance, a student used must
instead of will to express certainty. So, the sentence «...accidents will
happen» became «...accidents must happen», and «...a girl
can betray her lover» became «...a girl must betray her
lover».
The chart below shows the different confusions between
modals.
Chart 22: Confusion between modals
WRONG
MODAL
MODAL
MEANING
|
CAN
|
MAY
|
MUST
|
COULD
|
MIGHT
|
SHALL
|
SHOULD
|
WILL
|
WOULD
|
NOTHING
|
CAN
|
|
22
35.48%
|
7
11.29%
|
29
46.77%
|
18
29.09%
|
6
9.67%
|
10
16.12%
|
10
16.12%
|
8
12.92%
|
3
4.83%
|
MAY
|
16
25.80%
|
|
8
12.92%
|
19
30.64%
|
5
8.06%
|
6
9.67%
|
12
19.35%
|
19
30.64%
|
2
3.22%
|
5
8.06%3
|
MUST
|
13
20.96%
|
19
30.64%
|
|
16
25.80%
|
14
22.58%
|
10
16.12%
|
37
59.67%
|
14
22.58%
|
6
9.67%
|
3
4.83%
|
COULD
|
19
30.64%
|
15
25.19%
|
|
|
4
6.45%
|
3
4.83%
|
3
4.83%
|
5
8.06%
|
|
6
9.67%
|
MIGHT
|
|
|
|
|
|
2
3.22%
|
2
3.22%
|
1
1.61%
|
|
|
SHALL
|
9
14.51%
|
1
1.16%
|
|
11
17.74%
|
4
6.45%
|
|
4
6.45%
|
2
3.22%
|
|
|
SHOULD
|
5
8.06%
|
14
22.58%
|
20
32.25%
|
15
24.19%
|
17
27.41%
|
5
8.06%
|
|
11
17.74%
|
12
19.35%
|
5
8.06%
|
WILL
|
5
8.06%
|
7
11.29%
|
59
95.16%
|
20
32.25%
|
9
14.51%
|
4
6.45%
|
15
24.19%
|
|
12
19.35%
|
3
4.83%
|
WOULD
|
18
29.03%
|
14
22.58%
|
|
|
4
6.45%
|
1
1.61%
|
1
1.61%
|
4
6.45%
|
|
6
9.67%
|
The highest confusion lies between MUST and WILL: 95.16 % of
students misused MUST for WILL. 59.67 % of students used SHOULD where they had
to use MUST. Some modals are confused with others. The degree of confusions
follows:
Chart 23: Frequency of confusions between
modals
|
WILL
|
MUST
|
CAN
|
SHOULD
|
MAY
|
COULD
|
WOULD
|
SHALL
|
MIGHT
|
CASES
|
9
|
9
|
9
|
9
|
9
|
7
|
7
|
6
|
3
|
USES
|
134
|
132
|
113
|
104
|
92
|
55
|
48
|
31
|
5
|
The least known modal, that is the most confusing, is WILL as
it is used in 9 cases and 134 times. Then come MUST (9 cases, 132 uses), CAN (9
cases, 113 uses), SHOULD (9 cases, 104 uses).
If students confuse modals, it may be due to the fact that
many modals can be used to express the same idea or meaning without changing
the meaning of the sentence. Thus, the modals CAN or Will can be used to
express general request as in «...can/will you help me
with this job?». Also, the modals CAN/MAY/COULD/MIGHT can be used
to express «asking for permission as in «...can/may/could/might I go
now?». Some students prefer some modals to others.
III.2.2.5 - Students'
preferred modals
Students' modal preference is shown in the below chart.
Chart 24: Preference of modals
USE OF
RATHER
THAN
|
CAN
|
MAY
|
COULD
|
MIGHT
|
WILL
|
WOULD
|
CAN
|
|
35
56.45 %
|
5
8.06 %
|
22
35.48 %
|
4
6.45 %
|
|
MAY
|
25
40.32 %
|
|
5
8.06 %
|
22
35.48 %
|
|
|
COULD
|
13
20.94 %
|
17
27.41 %
|
|
28
35.48 %
|
|
5
8.06 %
|
MIGHT
|
11
17.74 %
|
16
25.80 %
|
5
8.06 %
|
|
|
|
WILL
|
28
45.16 %
|
|
|
|
|
|
WOULD
|
|
|
4
6.45 %
|
|
|
|
When students have the choice to use modals they prefer some
to others. On the chart, it appears that if students have the choice between
MAY and CAN, 40.32 % prefer CAN whereas 56.45 % opt for MAY. If they have the
choice between CAN and COULD, 8.06 % prefer COULD while 20.96 % will use CAN.
The degrees of preference between can, may, could, might, will, would are as
follows, decreasingly:
Chart 25: Frequency of preference of
modals
|
CAN
|
COULD
|
MAY
|
MIGHT
|
WOULD
|
WILL
|
CASES
|
4
|
4
|
3
|
3
|
1
|
1
|
USES
|
77
|
19
|
68
|
64
|
5
|
4
|
The preferred modal is CAN. In the current chart,
«cases» is the sum of the numbers taken vertically from the preceding
chart.
After the presentation of the different results of the
production, we shall comment the findings from these results on the production
of modals.
III.2.2.6 - Comments on
production
When we consider all the results we have found, we are bound
to say that students can't use the modal verbs appropriately. 41.93 % of
students fail to use the appropriate modals to express the deontic meaning,
while 64.51 % of students fail when it comes to the epistemic meanings. It
appears that students have more difficulties to express the epistemic meanings
than the deontic ones.
The students' level is very low regarding the average level of
the sample. Their level is fairly good when they are asked to express the
deontic meanings (3.79/7), insufficient when they have to express the epistemic
meanings (1.22/3) and when meanings are combined (3.98/10).
In general, students fail to use the modals to express
meanings. The level of students in production is insufficient (9/20).
The low scores of students may be due to their ignorance of
modals though they can be using modals as they were taught to do so. If some
students confuse modals, some do not try at all. The latter leave the blanks
maybe because of ignorance. Thus, in the test on production, there were 28
blanks left empty. That is, about 45.16 % of students leave a blank. The reason
they have blank may not be different from the one of students who refused to
take the test. Here again, there is the strategy of avoidance as in
recognition. The similarities between recognition and production bring us to
draw some general conclusions.
III.2.3 - Partial
conclusions and verification of the hypothesis
Our findings evidence that students don't master the English
modal auxiliary verbs since, averagely, 48.38 % get the average in our tests on
the English modals. The students' level is low since their average level on
modals is 9.54/20. A comparison of the two tests reveals that students can
identify the meanings of modals (53.22 %) more than they are able to produce
modals (43.54 %). Students understand the meanings of modals when they are
addressed but they cannot use modals to express their thoughts. Some students
do produce modals «correctly» or understand their meanings, however,
about 11 % of students use them haphazardly, which may bring them sometimes to
betray their thoughts. Those who do not want to say nonsense about modals
abstain. About 32.25 % of students abstain to react about modals, not to
mention those who did not take the test. Only 5.63 % of the students of first
year accepted to be tested. Girls seem to be more reluctant than boys regarding
modals, as only 3.22 % of the 465 girls of the class sat for the tests while
7.31 % of the 670 boys of first year took the tests. Among the testees, there
were only 2 repeaters of the class. Repeaters may believe they master modals,
although they need to be tested to confirm their belief.
We have also found that students do better in deontic meanings
than in epistemic ones. In fact, in recognition 50 % succeed in deontic
meanings versus 38.70 % in epistemic ones. As for production, 58.06 % succeed
in deontic versus 35.48 % in epistemic. These numbers may be attributed to
students' deontic tendency. As a matter of fact, we have found that 54.04 % of
students are inclined to deontic meanings though they confuse them with one
another.
There are also confusions between the deontic meanings and the
epistemic meanings. However, there is more confusion between the kinds of
meanings than between their types. Indeed, the highest confusion between the
kinds of meanings is 75.80 % (confusion between obligation and necessity),
70.96 % (confusion between probability and possibility); whereas the confusion
between the deontic meaning and the epistemic meaning is 53.22 %. We can
conclude that students misuse modals not because modals express both deontic
meaning and epistemic meanings, but because modals are subtle in the kinds of
meanings they express.
We discover further that students mix up meanings together as
well as modals. They do not master meanings and modals to the same level.
Talking of production, the least known modals are, decreasingly, WILL, MUST,
CAN etc., and the least known meanings are, decreasingly, probability,
giving permission, possibility etc. they confuse modals such as MUST with
WILL (95.16%), SHOULD with MUST (59.67%).
Students also prefer some modals to others. Thus, CAN is
preferred to COULD, COULD to MAY, etc.
As recognition is concerned, the least known modals are MUST,
MAY, SHOULD etc., and the least known meanings are, decreasingly,
obligation, advisability, giving permission etc.
It appears that the mastery of meanings or modals depends on
recognition and production. That is, there is a variation of knowledge
depending on, whether students are addressed or they address. They may
recognize some meanings, but be unable to use modals to express them.
III.3 - PROBABLE SOURCES OF MODAL
MISUSE AND MISUNDERSTANDING
The fact that students confuse meanings, or have tendency, or
fail to use right modals or right meanings or even avoid using modals has
multiple sources. The causes may be psychosocial, psychological or mere
ignorance.
Ignorance can be a source of the misuse of modals because if a
student has never met a modal or one of the meanings of modals, it is obvious
that he will not be able to use the modals appropriately. For example, if a
student doesn't know what is giving permission it is normal that he
uses WILL to express it. In our data, 22.58% students did so. Ignorance can
also be attributed to the fact that students have forgotten what they have
learnt in secondary school. They may had known what modals express and how
meanings are expressed but the lack of reading and practice may urge them to
forget modals; this may account for the low participation in the tests. Of
course, the misuses can be due to other factors.
If we look at the lack of mastery of modals from a
psychosocial angle, some external agents to students may favor the
misunderstandings or misuses of modals.
First of all, students may have been induced to errors by
their peers. While doing the test, students may have ignored some modals or
meanings and asked their peers to help them. The misleading can have happened
before the test or during the test. It may have happened during the test if the
student has attempted to cheat (some students did group work though they were
told not to do so). The misleading may have happened before the test if
students have been told so by a peer or by a teacher.
The relation between the teacher and the students is our
second concern in the psychosocial point of view. Indeed, students' misuse of
modals or misunderstanding of meanings can be attributed to teachers if the
latter taught the former erroneous meanings or if they failed to teach what
they had to. On the one hand, if the teacher himself doesn't master modals, he
will teach them erroneously and students will learn them defectively. On the
second hand, if the teacher does not explain the context of use of modals and
make students aware of the pragmatic meanings of modals, students will not be
able to use them appropriately.
The third aspect in our psychosocial reasons is the
interference of the mother tongue or French. We know that the testees are EFL
learners; so, they may be transferring the French modality system to English or
the modality system of their mother tongues since modality exist in all
languages but it is not expressed in the same way in all of them. A contractive
analysis of English modals and native languages modality systems would be
helpful to clear this point. Though other people may induce students to make
errors in the use and understanding of modals, students can misinterpret modals
by themselves. This may be due to their psychology.
The analysis of the data springs us to think that some
psychological reasons lead students to produce modals or to give them some
kinds of meanings. For instance, we have found that students have a deontic
tendency. This allows us to say that students pay more attention to social
events than to logic and mathematics. Their education may have conducted them
to be inclined to social use of modals. Furthermore, although we did not want
to do a comparative study between the use of modals by girls and by boys, the
recurrent occurrence of some elements struck our mind. We found that most of
the girls said that CAN expresses permission while most of boys said
that CAN expresses possibility. That makes us think that girls said so
because they are educated as housewives and they implicitly recognize the
existence of some authority to whom they will have to ask for permission. As
for boys, we think that they said so because they believe in power, strength
and accomplishment of their beliefs. We think that if there are differences
according to gender, the differences may be due to the fact that the psychology
of girls is different from that of boys.
In the end of our research there is evidence that students
have many difficulties to understand the meanings of modals and to use modals
appropriately, that there are more difficulties between the kinds of meanings
than within the types of meanings, that the difficulties exist more in the
deontic meanings, that few students use modals haphazardly, and that the causes
of misuses and misunderstandings are various.
However, in spite of the variety of sources and the miscellany
of difficulties, some suggestions can be made to improve the level of students
in the use and the understanding of modals. This is our concern in the
following chapter.
CHAPTER FOUR: RATIONALE OF
MODALS TEACHING AND LEARNING AND SOME SUGGESTIONS
Our suggestions are primarily addressed to teachers because
they are the mainspring of language teaching and learning system. They receive
instructions from textbook designers and from language teaching and learning
trainers. They have on charge to make students learn the language at the best.
Students can also benefit from these suggestions because they can be inspired
by our propositions. Textbooks designers and teacher supervisors can also
benefit from these suggestions since the former can consider them in their
textbooks and the latter in their training. Of course, researchers may evaluate
the efficiency of our propositions.
IV.1 - THE RATIONALE OF MODALS
TEACHING AND LEARNING
Before proposing how to teach modals, it may be necessary to
tell why students have to learn them. There are at least three reasons why
students should learn modals and use them instead of avoiding them.
First of all, as language learners, students must use English
approximately like native speakers. By using modals, students will sound more
like native speakers though they cannot be as fluent as them. For instance, by
saying «Could (instead of can) I talk to you a minute?» or
«Would (instead of will) you open the door?» the students will be
perceived less abrupt and aggressive with their request by English native
speakers, when they address someone who deserves respect.
The second reason why students must learn modals and use them
is that they enable them to express their thoughts accurately. If students want
to modalize their statements they must know the right modal to pass their idea
on to their addressors. They will not say «The teacher will come
today» when they mean «The teacher may come today».
Another reason is the authenticity and the economy of words.
Students must appear authentic in their expression by avoiding circumlocutions.
By using modals they make economy of words. Compare:
E.g. It's possible that I will go out to
dinner with my mother tonight.
(Six words)
Maybe I will go out to dinner with my
mother tonight.
(Three words)
I may go out to dinner with my mother
tonight.
(Only two words)
Now that we know the importance of modals, let's see how they
can best be taught.
IV.2 - SOME SUGGESTIONS IN
TEACHING MODALS
While teaching modals, the teacher should raise his students'
consciousness about some pragmatic concepts and show the differences between
the types of meanings and between the kinds of meanings. (cf section III.2.1.4
and III.2.1.5). We propose four steps for the teaching of modals.
IV.2.1 - Explicate the
context of the use of modals
Before teaching modals, the teacher himself should know what
are reference, presupposition, implicature and speech act. He should also know
the importance of these concepts in modals. In fact, by studying reference the
teacher should tell students who are the speaker, the addressor and the
addressee because the use of modals depends also on these participants.
Presupposition is important for the teaching of modals since through the study
of presupposition the image the speaker has of the subject or the importance
the speaker attaches to the subject are determined. Yet politeness partly
depends on the gap between the status of the speaker and that of the addressee.
As for implicature, it is useful in the teaching of modals because it enables
to know the intention of the speaker. Through the study of speech act the
teacher can tell the students the circumstances of the use of modals. To
summarize, the teacher needs to explicate the context of the use of modals
because the main way to understand the meaning of a modals is by its
context.
After defining the context to students, the teacher should
explain the differences between the types of meanings.
IV.2.2 - Explain the
differences between the types of meanings
The teacher should teach modals taking into account the
epistemic meaning and the deontic meaning. As William DUBOIS said in Syntaxe
du francais moderne (1932): «La langue est un perpétuel combat
entre la rationalité et l'affectivité»27(*); that is we use language to
express our own opinion while trying to be objective. In other words, language
is made of objectivity and subjectivity. The subjectivity refers to deontic
meaning and the objectivity, which is a subjective objectivity, refers to
epistemic meaning. Students must know the differences between these kinds of
meanings because the ignorance of these differences urges students to rush into
using modals. For instance, when they see the modal MUST, they say it expresses
obligation (74.19/%) 28(*) even if MUST expresses probability. The first
meaning is deontic and the second is epistemic.
The teacher should draw his students' attention on the
distinctive features of the types of meanings by asking them to find the
speaker's subject social status, the speaker's action orientation, the focus of
his intention, and to paraphrase the modals or to give their periphrastic
equivalences.
By stating the differences between the types of meanings the
teacher should put emphasis on the epistemic meaning while clarifying the
subtleties between the deontic meanings.
IV.2.3 - Explain the differences
between the kinds of meanings
After teaching the differences between the types of meanings,
the teacher should tell the differences between the kindss of meanings within
each type of meaning. He should tell the students the differences between
necessity and obligation, probability and possibility, necessity and
advisability, etc., and lay emphasis on meanings according to chart 12; and
more on those expressed by MUST, MAY, etc. according to chart 9.
IV.2.4- Encourage the use of modals
The teacher should encourage his students to use modals to
express meanings according to the scale given in chart 19. He should put
emphasis on the expression of probability, giving permission, possibility, etc.
by insisting on the use of WILL, MUST, CAN, etc. as shown in chart 23; and try
to balance their preference of modals taking into account the results of chart
25, that is make them use more the modals they prefer the least.
IV.2.5- Further suggestions
Unlike most textbooks which present modals by giving the modal
followed by its different meanings, we suggest that students should be taught
the meanings of modals. Instead of going from modal to meanings, we suggest to
go from meaning to modals. Instead of saying to students «MUST expresses
obligation», or «CAN expresses possibility»,
it would be better to say «obligation» is expressed by
MUST, SHALL and WILL». By doing so, students will be able to express their
thoughts and feelings.
The teacher should make students learn modals
actively. He may teach them vainly if he
spends his time teaching recognition of meanings such as
«What is the meaning of must in the following sentence?» The
teacher should train students to produce modals. We recognize that modals are
so many, and meanings are close one to the other, which make the mastery
difficult. The rule is «Practice makes perfect». Some practical
exercises are given in the appendix IV.
CONCLUSION
In this paper, we have assessed the use of the English modals
by first year students at the department of Anglophone Studies by means of an
experimental test as a device for data collection. Our investigation mainly
consisted in ascertaining whether the students of first year made differences
between the epistemic meanings and the deontic meanings of modals and whether
the incomprehension of the meanings of modals and their inappropriate uses
pertained to the fact that modals have both deontic and epistemic meanings.
In light of our survey, students were found to have a patchy
knowledge about the English modals. However, the incomprehension and the wrong
uses of modals were not found only in the types of meanings but also, and even
more in the kinds of meanings. We then made some suggestions to improve
students' knowledge of the English modals. We do not pretend that our
suggestions are the best ones. That is why we suggested that researchers and
practitioners would evaluate even more the validity of our suggestions.
This work was not done without difficulties. Constraints of
time and the lack of money limited our field of research. As an academic
dissertation the piece of research was to be completed within a reasonable time
limit; and as a student we could not take out subscriptions to many libraries
and websites. Additionally, there was a lack of experience to conduct research,
all the more so in English as we learned English as a foreign language.
Moreover, we have never been teacher. Our teaching suggestions may appear too
theoretical. In spite of these hindrances, this first experience in conducting
research was worthwhile and enjoyable and we do believe that the reached
results are reliable.
We hope that this paper will be of good avail to researchers
and teacher trainers and particularly to teachers who may find in this book a
new way of teaching modals. However, the suggestions should be adjusted to
their students' level. As for researchers, further research need to be done on
other modal words, modal-like forms, periphrastic modals, the past tense of
modals, negation with modals, answer to questions with modals; and some
contrastive studies of the use of modals by girls and boys, repeaters and
newcomers, English modality system and students' native languages modality
systems.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Brown, G. and Yule G. 1983. Discourse
Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Celce - Murcia, M. and Larsen - Freeman D.
1983. The Grammar Book: An ESL/EFL
Teachers' Course. Rowley, Massachussetts: Newbury
House Publishers Inc.
Cook, G. 1989. Discourse. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Crystal, D. (ed.) 1996. A Dictionary of
Linguistics and Phonetics. 4th ed. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Feigenbaum, I. 1985. The Grammar
Handbook. New York: Oxford University Press Inc.
Giglioli, P. P. (ed) 1972. Language and
Social Context. Harmondsworth, Middx: Penguin.
Huddleston, I.R. 1984. Introduction to the
Grammar of English. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Hudson, R.A. 2000. Sociolinguistics.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Krupp, J. and Tenuta L. 2002. The Modal
Book: Arround the World whith Joe and Lisa.
Montpellier: Pro Linga.
Leech, G. N. 1987. Meaning and the English
Verb. 2nd ed. London: Longman.
Levinson, S. 1983. Pragmatics.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lhérété, A. and Ploton J. M.
1990. L'anglais pratique: grammaire expliquée. Paris:
Longman France.
McCarthy, M. 1991. Discourse Analysis for
Language Teachers. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Palmer, F.R. 1986. Mood and Modality.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Powell, R. R. and Connaway. L. S. 2004.
Basic Research Methods for Librarians. 4th ed.
[C] Ronald R. Powell and Lynn Silipigni Connaway U.S.A.:
Library Unlimited.
www.lu.com
Richards, J. Platt,J. and Weber, H. 1985.
Longman Dictionary of Applied Linguistics. London: Longman.
Wardhaugh, R. 2003. Understanding English
Grammar: A Linguistic Approach.2nd ed.
Oxford: Basil Blacwell. Associates Publishers.
www.ProlinguaAssociates.com
Wehmeier, S., Lea D., Florio, J., Parkinson, D. and
Ashly,M. (ed). 1974. Oxford Advanced Learner's Dictionary of
Current English.3RD ed. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
2000. Oxford Advanced Learner's
Dictionary of Current English. 6th ed. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
APPENDIX I: FORMS OF
MODALS
FORMS OF MODALS
(i) Modals can occur with n't:
we mustn't do it.
(ii) They appear before other auxiliaries:
they should be going
(i) They serve as tags:
you can play football, can't you?
(ii) They do not co-occur:
*they might will come tomorrow
they might come tomorrow
(v) They never take a final s:
*she cans call you today
she can call you today
(vi) Modals have no non-finite form:
*she wants to can speak German
she wants to be able to speak German
(vii) They have no imperatives
*can be here!
(viii) MUST has no morphologically past tense form
Historically
Historically
Present tense forms past tense
forms
CAN COULD
WILL WOULD
MAY MIGHT
SHALL SHOULD
MUST /
(ix) There are suppletive negative forms
he may be there ___ he cant' be there
he must be there ___ he needn't be there
(x) There are formal differences between the modal verbs, in
their epistemic and deontic senses, in terms of negation and tense. The
negative form mustn't is generally used only deontically, as in: He
must be in his office. The only way of expressing the negative of epistemic
MUST is to use can't: He can't be in his office.
(xi) The verb which follows a modal is always in the base
form.
*He may comes next week.
He may come next week.
(xii) Short answers with modals never include the main verbs,
unless it is BE. But they always include any other auxiliaries.
Shouldn't he be there?
Yes, he should be.
Could they have gotten lost?
Yes, they could have.
Would we have been on time?
No, we wouldn't have been;
or
Yes, we wouldn't have.
(xiii) The negative is formed by putting not
after the modal auxiliary; the auxiliary do (do, does, or
did) is not used.
*she does not can speak English.
She cannot speak English.
(xiv) questions are formed by putting the auxiliary in front
of
the subject (s); the auxiliary do (do, does, or
did) is not
used.
*Does she may come.
May she come?
(xv) Sometimes both members of a pair (will/would,
shall/should, may/might, can/could) can be used in
describing a present or future
situation.
- present tense form; future situation.
Tomorrow, the car may be late.
- past tense form; future situation.
Tomorrow, the car might be late.
(xvi) There are several contractions.
Full forms contractions
(more formal) (less formal, to use in
conversation)
Will / shall 'll
Would / should 'd
Might not mightn't
Cannot/ can not can't
Could not couldn't
Shall not shan't
Should not shoudn't
Will not won't
Would not wouldn't
APPENDIX II: TESTS ON
MODALS
IDENTIFICATION OF THE STUDENT
Dot the square corresponding to your answer
Sex: F M
Are you repeating this class? YES
NO
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
TEST N° 1 (Recognition or comprehension)
PART ONE
Write the meaning of the modal for the sentences according to
the context: Invitation / Permission / Advisability / Necessity / Obligation /
General request /Asking for permission.
e.g. [The teacher is talking to Bob]
Bob, you may leave the room Meaning
Permission
1-You should marry her if you want to be happy.
Meaning .........
2-You must see a doctor, father. Meaning
.........
3-You shall go to school because I (father) say so.
Meaning .........
4- Shall we meet tonight? There is a dancing party to John's.
Meaning .........
5- You may smoke here, I don't mind.
Meaning.........
6- Must I answer these questions?
Meaning .........
7- May they go with us? I want your opinion.
Meaning .........
PART TWO
Write the meaning of the modal for the sentences according to
the context: Possibility / Probability / Certainty.
e.g. That can be true.
Meaning possibility
1-They should be waiting for her. They're late.
Meaning ............
2-The illness might be fatal.
Meaning ............
3-That will be Dick. I was expecting him to call me.
[On hearing the telephone ring]
Meaning ............
PART THREE
Write the meaning of the modal for the sentences according to
the context: Asking for Permission / Possibility / General Request / Giving
permission / Necessity / Probability / Obligation / Certainty / Advisability /
Invitation.
1- They must know that. Meaning
..........
2- He should be in Paris by now. (Because his plane took off
early) Meaning .........
3- James will sing at the party. (Because he always does)
Meaning .........
4- You can swim. Meaning
.........
5- You may leave. (Now that you have answered my questions)
Meaning .........
6- He must have a wife. (Because he said he was married)
Meaning .........
7- He will go to war. (Or my name is not Captain Blood)
Meaning .........
8- You should tell your parents about this. (Because they can
guide you) Meaning .........
9- You may go tomorrow. (Or you may not_ I'm not sure)
Meaning .........
10- He must do it. (Or we are lost)
Meaning .........
TEST N°2 (PRODUCTION)
PART FOUR
Use the right modal for the sentences according to the meaning
indicated between square brackets: Can / Will / Shall / Must / Could / Would /
Might / Should / May.
e.g. «What would you say if you want to tell a close
friend who needs money for an emergency that one possibility is for him
to sell his bicycle?»
- You should sell your bicycle. Meaning
[Advisability]
1- [Teacher talking to student] «you .......do your
homework before coming to class» Meaning
[obligation]
2 - [It is not forbidden] «You................ smoke
here» Meaning [permission]
3 - I think that your girlfriend does not write to you enough.
I recommend her to do so. Therefore, I say,
«Your girlfriend............write you letters».
Meaning [advisability]
4 - Honey, you are very sick, you..............take these
tablets
to feel well Meaning [necessity]
5 - [You want to invite your friend to a party.] You say,
«..............we meet on Monday?»
Meaning [invitation]
6 - Sir, I have been waiting for hours, ............ I go now?
Meaning [asking for permission]
7 - You want to know if it is possible that a friend helps
you:
«...............you help me with this job?»
Meaning [general request]
PART FIVE
Use the right modal for the sentences according to the meaning
indicated between square brackets: Can / Will / May / Shall / Must / Could /
Would / Might / Should.
e.g.1. Someone is knocking at the door. That could be Sali.
Meaning [weak inference]
e.g.2. someone is knocking at the door. That should be Sali.
Meaning [very strong inference]
1 - The meat.......be ready by now, though it may need
a few more minutes. Meaning
[probability]
2 - It.......rain tomorrow. I'm 100% certain of it.
Meaning [certainty]
3 - It.......rain tomorrow. I'm 50% certain of it
Meaning [possibility]
PART SIX
Use the right modal for the sentences according to the meaning
indicated between square brackets: Can / Will / May / Shall / Must / Could
/ Would / Might / Should.
1 - .......you lend me your pen? (I want your
willingness.) Meaning [general request]
2 - You.......go to school, (whether you like it or not.)
Meaning [obligation]
3 - I remember that the teacher has repeated this rule over
and over again; I shall no longer study other rules.
The test.......be about this rule (this is my conclusion)
Meaning [probability]
4 - Student A: «.......you come back by the end of the
week?»
Student B: «I am afraid; my mother will not allow me
to.» Meaning [permission]
5 - My son, why do you tell that girl all your secrets?
Don't you know that a girl.......betray her lover?
Meaning [possibility]
6 - It is a characteristic fact about life that accidents
happen.
So, whatever you do, accidents....... happen.
(you cannot avoid them) Meaning
[certainty]
7 - They.......study at least five hours tonight if they want
to graduate. Meaning
[advisability]
8 - She.......be here. Meaning
[possibility or permission]
9 - A person.......have a valid passport in order to travel
to foreign countries. Meaning
[necessity]
10 - He.......be in his office. Meaning
[obligation or probability]
APPENDIX III:
CORRECTION OF THE TESTS
IDENTIFICATION OF THE STUDENT
Dot the square corresponding to your answer
Sex: F M
Are you repeating this class? YES
NO
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
TEST N° 1 (Recognition or comprehension)
PART ONE
Write the meaning of the modal for the sentences according to
the context: Invitation / Permission / Advisability / Necessity / Obligation /
General request /Asking for permission.
e.g. [The teacher is talking to Bob]
Bob, you may leave the room Meaning
Permission
1-You should marry her if you want to be happy.
Meaning: Advisability
2-You must see a doctor, father. Meaning:
Necessity
3-You shall go to school because I (father) say so.
Meaning: Obligation
4- Shall we meet tonight? There is a dancing party to John's.
Meaning: Invitation
5- You may smoke here, I don't mind.
Meaning: Giving permission
6- Must I answer these questions? Meaning:
General request
7- May they go with us? I want your opinion.
Meaning: Asking for permission
PART TWO
Write the meaning of the modal for the sentences according to
the context: Possibility/Probability /Certainty.
e.g. That can be true.
Meaning: Possibility
1 - They should be waiting for her. They're late.
Meaning: Probability
2 - The illness might be fatal.
Meaning: Possibility
3 - That will be Dick. I was expecting him to call me.
Meaning: Certainty
[On hearing the telephone ring]
PART THREE
Write the meaning of the modal for the sentences according to
the context: Asking for Permission / Possibility / General Request / Giving
permission / Necessity / Probability / Obligation / Certainty / Advisability /
Invitation.
1 - They must know that. Meaning:
Obligation/Probability
2 - He should be in Paris by now.
(Because his plane took off early)
Meaning: Probability
3 - James will sing at the party. (Because he always does)
Meaning: Certainty
4 - You can swim. Meaning:
Possibility/Giving permission
5 - You may leave.
(Now that you have answered my questions)
Meaning: Giving permission
6 - He must have a wife.
(Because he said he was married)
Meaning: Probability
7 - He will go to war.
(Or my name is not Captain Blood)
Meaning: Obligation
8 - You should tell your parents about this.
(Because they can guide you) Meaning:
Advisability
9 - You may go tomorrow.
(Or you may not_ I'm not sure) Meaning:
Possibility
10 - He must do it. (Or we are lost)
Meaning: Necessity
TEST N°2 (PRODUCTION)
PART FOUR
Use the right modal for the sentences according to the meaning
indicated between square brackets: Can / Will / Shall / Must / Could / Would /
Might / Should / May.
e.g. «What would you say if you want to tell a close
friend who needs money for an emergency that one possibility is for him
to sell his bicycle?»
- You should sell your bicycle.
Meaning [Advisability]
1 - [Teacher talking to student] «You must do your
homework before coming to class»
Meaning [obligation]
2 - [It is not forbidden] «You can smoke
here» Meaning [permission]
3 - I think that your girlfriend does not write to you enough.
I recommend her to do so. Therefore, I say,
«Your girlfriend should write you
letters». Meaning [advisability]
4 - Honey, you are very sick, you must take
these tablets to feel well
Meaning [necessity]
5 - [You want to invite your friend to a party.]
You say, «Shall we meet on Monday?»
Meaning [invitation]
6 - Sir, I have been waiting for hours,
might/may/can/could I go now? Meaning
[asking for permission]
7 - You want to know if it is possible that a friend helps
you:
«Can/will you help me with this job?»
Meaning [general request]
PART FIVE
Use the right modal for the sentences according to the meaning
indicated between square brackets: Can / Will / May / Shall / Must / Could /
Would / Might / Should.
e.g.1. Someone is knocking at the door. That could be Sali.
Meaning [weak inference]
e.g.2. someone is knocking at the door. That should be Sali.
Meaning [very strong inference]
1 - The meat should be ready by now, though it may need
a few more minutes. Meaning
[probability]
2 - It will rain tomorrow. I'm 100% certain of it.
Meaning [certainty]
3 - It may rain tomorrow. I'm 50% certain of it.
Meaning [possibility]
PART SIX
Use the right modal for the sentences according to the meaning
indicated between square brackets: Can / Will / May / Shall / Must / Could
/ Would / Might / Should.
1 - Could/would you lend me your pen? (I want your
willingness.)Meaning [general request]
2 - You will go to school, (whether you like it or
not.) Meaning [obligation]
3 - I remember that the teacher has repeated this rule over
and over again; I shall no longer study other rules.
The test must be about this rule (this is my
conclusion) Meaning [probability]
4 - Student A: «May you come back by the end of
the week?»
Student B: «I am afraid; my mother will not allow me
to.» Meaning [permission]
5 - My son, why do you tell that girl all your secrets?
Don't you know that a girl can betray her lover?
Meaning [possibility]
6 - It is a characteristic fact about life that accidents
happen.
So, whatever you do, accidents will happen.
(You cannot avoid them) Meaning
[certainty]
7 - They should study at least five hours tonight if
they want
to graduate. Meaning
[advisability]
8 - She may be here.
Meaning [possibility or permission]
9 - A person must have a valid passport in order to
travel
to foreign countries. Meaning
[necessity]
10 - He must be in his office. Meaning
[obligation or probability]
APPENDIX IV:
PRACTICE
The following suggestions are an excerpt from the work by
Larsen-Freeman and Celce-Murcia. The authors are making suggestions to
teachers:
TEACHING SUGGESTIONS
1 - Several of the social interactional modals form a
continuum from «weak suggestion» to order «commands!» this
pattern can be taught both formally and informally using thermometers as visual
aids to show the degree of necessity involved. (Remember that the different
forms do not necessarily have equal semantic distance between them.)
WILL
MUST HAFTA (HAVE TO)
HAD BETTER BETTER (had better)
SHOULD OUGHTA (ought to)
MIGHT
COULD
FORMAL
INFORMAL
Students would then be given hypothetical situations to
respond. They would have to decide whether (a) the situation is formal or
informal. (b) which degree of strength is called for. (Note: If one thermometer
is used with, say, beginners, step (a) is not necessary.) For example:
do
What will you say
if...........
Would
a. You are a teacher who wants to let a certain student know
that it is essential to come
to class on time.
b. You want to tell a close friend who needs money for
emergency that one possibility
is for him to sell his car.
c. A fellow professor is not being paid the proper salary, and
you think it would help if he saw the Dean.
2 - Other uses of social interactional modals can be taught
using dialogs. E.g.:
Teacher; Class, for tomorrow you will read Chapter 4
and do the exercises for that chapter.
Student X: (at the end of class) I can do all those
exercises. Would you please give me
another assignment?
Teacher: Do the first exercise anyway. But you may
write an easy instead of doing the
others.
Student X: Thank you. That's what I'll do.
3 - One of the uses of the logical probability modals is to
predict something such as the chance of
rain tomorrow. Show your students what degree of prediction
is expressed by each modal:
(possibility) weak, outside chance: It (could, might)
rain tomorrow.
(perhaps) stronger chance: It may very
well rain tomorrow.
(probably) strong chance: It probably
will rain tomorrow.
(likely)
(certainly) certainty: It will
rain tomorrow.
a. For oral practice, have students express (using a modal)
situations such as the following with the degree of prediction suggested by the
context (or the teacher):
(1) There's a 30 percent chance of rain tomorrow.
(2) There's an 80 percent chance of rain later today.
(3) The probability of good weather this coming weekend.
(4) The probability of man's landing on Mars during the next
20 years.
b. For written practice, have students read a paragraph or
essay using modals predictively.
Get them to describe in their own words the degree of each
prediction. Have them write their own essay on a parallel topic.
4 - The other main use of the logical modals is to make
inferences (guesses) about current
state/situations. Give your students a modal paradigm. E.g.:
Someone's knocking at the door.
weak inference: That could/might be Sydney.
stronger inference: That may be Sydney.
strong inference: That should be Sydney.
very strong inference: That must be Sydney.
absolute certainty in making an inference (rare): That will
be Sydney.
a. For oral practice, have students react to situations (using
a modal) such as the following:
(1) Student X is not in class today.
(2) Student Y is falling asleep/is thinking of something
else.
(3) The local football star has not been playing as well as
usual.
b. For written practice, one might try translation from the
student's native language into
English or vice versa as a check on comprehension (i.e.,
reading) and production
(i.e.,writing).
(Celce-Murcia,M. and Larsen-Freeman D. 1983. The Grammar
Book: An ESL/EFL Teachers' Course. Rowley, Massachussetts: Newbury House
Publishers Inc. p.p. 89-91)
* 1 Levinson (1983:1)
* 2 Ibid
* 3 Brown and Yule (1983:192)
* 4 Ibid.
* 5 Levinson,op.cit.
* 6 Ibid.
* 7 Brown and Yule, op.cit.
p37
* 8 Giglioli (1972:22-23)
* 9Palmer (1986:10)
* 10 Ibid.
* 11 Ibid.
* 12 Lorsqu'on s'exprime on
peut:
Soit viser l'objectivité
Soit laisser parler sa subjectivité
Dans le premier cas, l'énonciateur rend compte des
événementss à la manière d'un historien qui
s'efface derriere la réalité
Dans le deuxième cas, l'énonciateur raconte
à l'auditeur ou au lecteur les faits tels qu'il les perçoit
à travers le filtre de sa sensabikité.
On appelle modalité la présence de ce filtrage
exercé par l'énonciateur.
* 13 McCarthy (1991:85)
* 14 Palmer, op. cit.
* 15 Ibid.
* 16 Ibid.
* 17 Ibid.
* 18Celce-Murcia and
.Larsen-Freeman (1983:83)
* 19 See section I.2.0
* 20 Palmer, o.p. cit.p33
* 21 See Appendix I
* 22 CAN has a third use when
it expresses ability. It is the dynamic use (Palmer,op.cit. p102)
* 23 Ibid. p 10
* 24 Ibid. p 97
* 25 Ibid.
* 26 Celce-Murcia and Larsen
Freeman, o.p. cit. p85
* 27
Lhérété and Ploton (1990 :132)
* 28 See section III.2.2.1.2
|